From Casetext: Smarter Legal Research

Donaldson v. State

SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA
Dec 17, 2012
367 Mont. 228 (Mont. 2012)

Opinion

No. DA 11–0451.

2012-12-17

Jan DONALDSON and Mary Anne Guggenheim, Mary Leslie and Stacey Haugland, Gary Stallings and Rick Wagner, Kellie Gibson and Denise Boettcher, John Michael Long and Richard Parker, Nancy Owens and MJ Williams, Plaintiffs and Appellants, v. STATE of Montana, Defendant and Appellee.

Section 27–8–202, MCA. The Act further provides, however, that this enumeration “does not limit or restrict the exercise of the general powers conferred in 27–8–201 in any proceeding where declaratory relief is sought in which a judgment or decree will terminate the controversy or remove an uncertainty.” Section 27–8–205, MCA. The Act “is to be liberally construed and administered,” § 27–8–102, MCA, and “[n]o action or proceeding shall be open to objection on the ground that a declaratory judgment or decree is prayed for,” § 27–8–201, MCA. Spates, 590 A.2d at 1077.



OPINION and ORDER



¶ 1 Plaintiffs are individuals from a variety of professional backgrounds who are in committed same-sex relationships. In 2010 they sued the State of Montana, complaining that they are unable to obtain protections and benefits that are available to similarly-situated different-sex couples who marry under State law. Plaintiffs expressly do not challenge Montana law's restriction of marriage to heterosexual couples, do not seek the opportunity to marry, and do not seek the designation of marriage for their relationships. They contend however that there is a “statutory structure” in Montana law that prohibits them from enjoying “significant relationship and family protections and obligations automatically provided to similarly-situated different-sex couples who marry.”

¶ 2 Plaintiffs contend that this statutory structure interferes with their rights under Article II of the Montana Constitution, including their rights to equal protection, due process, and the rights to privacy, dignity and the pursuit of life's necessities. They seek a declaration that the State's failure to provide them access to the statutory scheme available to different-sex couples denies them the rights guaranteed by Article II. They seek an injunction prohibiting the State from continuing to deny them access to the statutory scheme.

¶ 3 The District Court denied Plaintiffs' motion for summary judgment and granted the State's motion to dismiss under M.R. Civ. P. 12(b)(6). The District Court noted that Plaintiffs do not seek a declaration that any specific statutes are unconstitutional. The District Court concluded that granting the relief sought—ordering the Legislature to enact a statutory scheme to address Plaintiffs' goals of achieving equal treatment—would be an inappropriate exercise of judicial power. Doing so, according to the District Court, would run afoul of the separation of powers required by Article III, section 1 of the Montana Constitution.

¶ 4 The District Court was also concerned that granting broad declaratory relief would likely impact a large number of statutes in potentially unknown and unintended ways. In the District Court proceedings Plaintiffs parenthetically listed a number of Montana statutes that they contend are within the “statutory scheme” that denies them equal access to rights and responsibilities. The District Court concluded, however that “what plaintiffs want here is not a declaration of the unconstitutionality of a specific statute or set of statutes but rather a direction to the legislature to enact a statutory arrangement.” The District Court determined that while this had some appeal, such relief was “unprecedented and uncharted in Montana law.” The District Court concluded that “the proper ways to deal with Plaintiffs' concerns are specific suits directed at specific, identifiable statutes.” Plaintiffs appealed after the District Court denied their motion to alter or amend.

¶ 5 On appeal Plaintiffs argue, without reference to specific statutes, that they are “excluded from the statutory scheme of benefits and obligations the state has associated exclusively with marriage.” Plaintiffs contend that a strict level of review is required, but that even at the lowest levels of constitutional scrutiny the State cannot show a legitimate governmental interest in the current statutory scheme, and that it violates their rights under Article II of the Montana Constitution. Plaintiffs contend that the State excludes them from access to unnamed benefits and obligations in violation of Montana's constitutional rights of privacy, dignity and the pursuit of life's basic necessities. Plaintiffs contend that they are entitled to a declaratory judgment and to injunctive relief to redress the violation of their rights. Plaintiffs contend that while they can obtain relief without a judicial order requiring the Legislature to act, such an order is a remedy well within established constitutional bounds.

¶ 6 Plaintiffs ask that the judgment of the District Court be reversed and the case remanded to grant Plaintiffs' motion for summary judgment as well as a declaratory judgment and injunction. We affirm in part, reverse in part and remand for further proceedings.

¶ 7 As a general rule, this Court will not disturb a district court's determination that declaratory relief is not necessary or proper unless the district court abused its discretion. Miller v. State Farm, 2007 MT 85,¶ 5, 337 Mont. 67, 155 P.3d 1278 (citing Northfield Ins. v. Mont. Assoc. of Counties, 2000 MT 256, ¶ 8, 301 Mont. 472, 10 P.3d 813). We review a district court's interpretation of law to determine whether the interpretation is correct. Miller, ¶ 5.

¶ 8 In the past Montana courts have held specific statutes unconstitutional, and in some cases have directed the Legislature to act to comply with specific duties. Helena Elementary School Dist. No. 1 v. State, 236 Mont. 44, 769 P.2d 684 (school funding); Snetsinger v. Mont. Univ. System, 2004 MT 390, 325 Mont. 148, 104 P.3d 445 (provision of employment benefits). In the present case, however, Plaintiffs do not seek a declaration that any particular statute is unconstitutional or that its implementation should be enjoined. Rather, Plaintiffs seek a general declaration of their rights and seek orders enjoining the State to provide them a “legal status and statutory structure” that protects their rights.

¶ 9 We agree with the District Court that Plaintiffs' requested relief exceeds the bounds of a justiciable controversy, Gryczan v. State, 283 Mont. 433, 442, 942 P.2d 112, 117 (1997), and decline to provide the declaratory relief requested. It is the opinion of this Court that the broad injunction and declaratory judgment sought by Plaintiffs would not terminate the uncertainty or controversy giving rise to this proceeding. Instead, a broad injunction and declaration not specifically directed at any particular statute would lead to confusion and further litigation. As the District Court aptly stated: “For this Court to direct the legislature to enact a law that would impact an unknown number of statutes would launch this Court into a roiling maelstrom of policy issues without a constitutional compass.” A district court may refuse to enter a declaratory judgment if it would not terminate the uncertainty or controversy giving rise to the proceedings, § 27–8–206, MCA; Miller, ¶ 7. Courts do not function, even under the Declaratory Judgments Act, to determine speculative matters, to enter anticipatory judgments, to declare social status, to give advisory opinions or to give abstract opinions. Mont. Dept. Nat. Res. & Cons. v. Intake Water Co., 171 Mont. 416, 440, 558 P.2d 1110, 1123 (1976).

¶ 10 In addition, declaring the parameters of constitutional rights is a serious matter. This Court, for example, avoids deciding constitutional issues whenever possible. Weidow v. Uninsured Employers' Fund, 2010 MT 292, ¶ 22, 359 Mont. 77, 246 P.3d 704. Statutes are presumed to be constitutional. Oberson v. U.S. Forest Service, 2007 MT 293, ¶ 14, 339 Mont. 519, 171 P.3d 715. That presumption can only be overcome after careful consideration of the purpose and effect of the statute, employing the proper level of scrutiny. Oberson, ¶ 22 (analyzing the constitutionality of the snowmobile liability statute, § 23–2–653, MCA). Broadly determining the constitutionality of a “statutory scheme” that may, according to Plaintiffs, involve hundreds of separate statutes, is contrary to established jurisprudence.

¶ 11 This Court may fashion the relief warranted by any appeal. Section 3–2–204, MCA. It is this Court's opinion that Plaintiffs should be given the opportunity, if they choose to take it, to amend the complaint and to refine and specify the general constitutional challenges they have proffered. For example, the record contains several affidavits from the named Plaintiffs and others that assert that they have suffered discrimination from the State's failure to recognize their relationships. While Plaintiffs' brief listed Title 40 of the Montana Code as an area of family law that furthers such discrimination, the dismissal of this action because of Plaintiffs' broad claims has precluded the development of claims that specific statutes promote or cause discrimination. These are important issues and should be decided only after the statutes involved are specifically identified and specifically analyzed in district court proceedings.

¶ 12 Montana law generally favors allowing a party to amend its pleadings. Rule 15, M.R. Civ. P.; Hobble–Diamond Cattle Co. v. Triangle Irrig. Co., 249 Mont. 322, 325, 815 P.2d 1153, 1155 (1991); Aldrich & Co. v. Ellis, 2002 MT 177, ¶ 27, 311 Mont. 1, 52 P.3d 388 (remand to allow plaintiff to add claim). The purpose of amending a complaint is to give the defendant adequate notice of the plaintiff's claims. Kudloff v. City of Billings, 260 Mont. 371, 375, 860 P.2d 140, 142 (1993). The decision to allow a plaintiff to amend a complaint is essentially an equitable one. Stundal v. Stundal, 2000 MT 21, ¶ 17, 298 Mont. 141, 995 P.2d 420, and leave to amend may be denied when the amendment would be futile or legally insufficient. Hickey v. Baker School Dist. No. 12, 2002 MT 322, ¶ 33, 313 Mont. 162, 60 P.3d 966.

¶ 13 The Plaintiffs should be afforded the opportunity to amend their complaint and to develop an argument as to the nature of the State's interest in advancing specific laws as well as the level of constitutional scrutiny that should be applied to those laws by the courts. Plaintiffs of course may choose to not amend, and that decision is theirs to make. If they do amend they will need to choose what statute or statutes to put in issue and upon what legal grounds. The dissent may be disappointed in the majority's approach to this case. However, that does not change the fact that the Plaintiffs chose to pursue an overly broad request for a declaratory judgment and injunctive relief, without developing a factual record in the District Court and without identifying a specific statute or statutes that impose the discrimination they allege.

¶ 14 For the reasons set out above, the decision of the District Court is affirmed in part, reversed in part and remanded for further proceedings consistent with this opinion, in a schedule to be determined by the District Court.

¶ 15 The Clerk is directed to provide copies hereof to all counsel of record and to the Honorable Jeffrey M. Sherlock, District Judge.

Justice JIM RICE, concurring.

¶ 16 I join in the Court's decision affirming the District Court. I agree with the Court and the District Court that the remedy sought in Plaintiffs' prayer for relief—that the court issue an order requiring the State to offer Plaintiffs “a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations that the State provides to different-sex couples who marry”—is overly broad and not justiciable. Opinion, ¶ 8. Further, I have no objection to remanding the case to allow Plaintiffs an opportunity to amend their pleadings to start the case anew. Opinion, ¶¶ 12–13. This is the procedural equivalent to filing a different legal challenge after dismissal of a case, which the Plaintiffs are entitled to pursue. Thus, I have signed the Court's Opinion.

¶ 17 I write separately to address the District Court's analysis of the Marriage Amendment to the Montana Constitution, and to explain the Amendment's application to Plaintiffs' substantive equal protection contentions set forth in Count I of their complaint. I believe that the Amendment provides another basis to affirm the District Court's dismissal of Count I, in addition to the overly broad nature of the relief sought.

¶ 18 The District Court reasoned that, while “this Court does not necessarily feel that Montana's marriage amendment bars it from acting,” nonetheless “the existence of the marriage amendment plays into the jurisprudential decision that Plaintiffs' requested relief constitutes an impermissible sojourn into the powers of the legislative branch.” I agree that the Marriage Amendment is applicable, but believe the District Court understated its significance. With its passage, the law's historical designation of marriage as between a man and a woman—and the exclusive treatment premised thereon—became an expressly constitutional classification.

¶ 19 Count I alleges that “Plaintiffs are similarly situated in every material respect to [ ] different-sex couples” and that the State's exclusion of Plaintiffs from the benefits and obligations “that the State offers to similarly-situated different-sex couples through the legal status of marriage impermissibly subjects Plaintiffs to unequal treatment” and constitutes “State discrimination.” With all due respect to Plaintiffs, I believe their equal protection claim must fail under longstanding and deeply rooted legal principles, in both Montana and national jurisprudence. Under the law, discussed below, marriage between a man and woman is a unique relationship, dissimilar to all other relationships and alone essential to the nation's foundation and survival, and the State errs neither by recognizing it as such nor by giving it exclusive treatment. In sum, it is not discrimination to treat uniquely that which is unique.

¶ 20 Plaintiffs emphasize that they are not seeking the right to marry, but nonetheless claim in Count I that they are entitled to all of the “protections, rights, benefits, duties, responsibilities, and obligations” which the State grants based upon marriage. During oral argument, Plaintiffs' counsel acknowledged that the relief sought would strip from the law the exclusive treatment of marriage as a basis for providing any concrete legal benefit. The only exclusive meaning left to marriage, counsel said, would be aspirational: “How people view it, how symbolic and how important and how solemn it is.” The question thus posed by Plaintiffs' equal protection claim is whether the State is barred by the Constitution from using marriage as an exclusive basis for granting any concrete legal entitlement.

¶ 21 As we have explained, “[t]he first step in an equal protection analysis is to ‘identify the classes involved, and determine if they are similarly situated.’ ” Jaksha v. Butte–Silver Bow Co., 2009 MT 263, ¶ 16, 352 Mont. 46, 214 P.3d 1248 (citation omitted). “ ‘If the classes are not similarly situated, then ... it is not necessary for us to analyze the challenge further.’ ” Kershaw v. Dept. of Transp., 2011 MT 170, ¶ 17, 361 Mont. 215, 257 P.3d 358. The classes here have been identified as same-sex couples, represented by Plaintiffs, and married couples. To analyze whether these classes are similarly situated, I begin by summarizing the extensive jurisprudence on the issue of marriage, particularly, as it stood when Montanans were asked to adopt the Marriage Amendment, and then turn to the Amendment itself.

¶ 22 It is so well established that marriage between a man and a woman is a fundamental constitutional right I need not belabor the point. See Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 95, 107 S.Ct. 2254, 2265, 96 L.Ed.2d 64 (1987) (“[T]he decision to marry is a fundamental right”); Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 384, 98 S.Ct. 673, 680, 54 L.Ed.2d 618 (1978) (quoting Meyer v. Neb., 262 U.S. 390, 399, 43 S.Ct. 625, 626, 67 L.Ed. 1042 (1923)) (“the right ‘to marry, establish a home and bring up children’ is a central part of the liberty protected by the Due Process Clause”); Conaway v. Deane, 401 Md. 219, 932 A.2d 571, 618 n. 63 (2007) (citations omitted) (“It is beyond doubt that the right to marry is a fundamental liberty interest protected by the Constitution.”). Likewise, this Court has stated, “[w]e too have recognized that marriage is a fundamental right.” State v. Guill, 2011 MT 32, ¶ 66, 359 Mont. 225, 248 P.3d 826.

See also Loving v. Va., 388 U.S. 1, 12, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 (1967); Cleveland Bd. of Educ. v. LaFleur, 414 U.S. 632, 639–40, 94 S.Ct. 791, 795, 39 L.Ed.2d 52 (1974); Montgomery v. Carr, 101 F.3d 1117, 1124 (6th Cir.1996).

¶ 23 Marriage between a man and woman has been declared a fundamental right because of the critical functions it performs and the purposes it fulfills for the greater society. “[M]arriage involves interests of basic importance in our society.” Boddie v. Conn., 401 U.S. 371, 376, 91 S.Ct. 780, 785, 28 L.Ed.2d 113 (1971) (citations omitted). Marriage is “the relationship that is the foundation of the family in our society.” Zablocki, 434 U.S. at 386, 98 S.Ct. at 681. Maintenance of marriage is an issue in which “the public is deeply interested, for it is the foundation of the family and of society, without which there would be neither civilization nor progress.” Maynard v. Hill, 125 U.S. 190, 210–11, 8 S.Ct. 723, 729, 31 L.Ed. 654 (1888). Our Court has explained that “upon [marriage's] permanence depends the family, the foundation of the home, ‘upon the preservation of which, in turn, depends good citizenship and the permanency of a republican form of government.’ ” Walker v. Hill, 90 Mont. 111, 124, 300 P. 260, 263–64 (1931) (citations omitted); accord Franklin v. Franklin, 40 Mont. 348, 350, 106 P. 353, 354 (1910) (Upon marriage “depends the home, upon the preservation of which, in turn, depends good citizenship and the permanency of a republican form of government. The state therefore favors the institution of marriage”). “Marriage is a foundation stone in the bedrock of our state and communities.” Cook v. Cook, 209 Ariz. 487, 104 P.3d 857, 862, ¶ 18 (2005).

See also Maynard, 125 U.S. at 211–12, 8 S.Ct. at 730 (quoting Adams v. Palmer, 51 Me. 480, 485 (Me.1863)) (marriage is “a ‘relation the most important ... the first step from barbarism to incipient civilization, the purest tie of social life and the true basis of human progress' ”); Griswold v. Conn., 381 U.S. 479, 486, 85 S.Ct. 1678, 1682, 14 L.Ed.2d 510 (1965) (“Marriage is a coming together for better or for worse, hopefully enduring, and intimate to the degree of being sacred. It is an association .... for as noble a purpose as any involved in our prior decisions.”); Reynolds v. U.S., 98 U.S. 145, 165, 25 L.Ed. 244 (1879) (“Upon [marriage] ... society may be said to be built”).

¶ 24 Beyond these reasons of family, societal stability, governance and progress, as important as they are, courts analyzing marriage have focused upon even more compelling reasons: its exclusive role in procreation and in insuring the survival, protection and thriving of the human race. Marriage is “ ‘fundamental to our very existence and survival.’ ” Guill, ¶ 66 (quoting Loving v. Va., 388 U.S. 1, 12, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 1824, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 (1967)). “Marriage and procreation are fundamental to the very existence and survival of the race.” Skinner v. Okla. ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541, 62 S.Ct. 1110, 1113, 86 L.Ed. 1655 (1942). “[V]irtually every [U.S.] Supreme Court case recognizing as fundamental the right to marry indicates as the basis for the conclusion the institution's inextricable link to procreation, which necessarily and biologically involves participation (in ways either intimate or remote) by a man and a woman.” Conaway v. Deane, 401 Md. 219, 932 A.2d 571, 621 (2007). “All of the cases infer that the right to marry enjoys its fundamental status due to the male-female nature of the relationship and/or the attendant link to fostering procreation of our species.” Conaway, 932 A.2d at 619 (citing the Supreme Court's holdings in Loving,Zablocki,Turner, and Skinner ).

¶ 25 From procreation springs further societal protections provided exclusively by marriage. As noted above, courts have cited the raising of children to be one of the core functions which support constitutional protectionof marriage. See Meyer v. Neb., 262 U.S. at 399, 43 S.Ct. at 626;see also Baker v. Nelson, 291 Minn. 310, 191 N.W.2d 185, 186 (1971), appeal dismissed,409 U.S. 810, 93 S.Ct. 37, 34 L.Ed.2d 65 (1972) ( “The institution of marriage as a union of man and woman, uniquely involving the procreation and rearing of children within a family, is as old as the book of Genesis.”) (emphasis added). Married couples role-model and thereby teach procreative relationships and the procreative lifestyle to children of the marriage as they are raised, ensuring that marriage's human race-sustaining functions upon which the survival and stability of society depend are passed to and replicated by the next generation.

¶ 26 The replication, by children, of the procreative marital relationship as role-modeled by their married parents not only perpetuates the race-sustaining function by populating the race, but also builds extended families which share hereditary characteristics of a common gene pool. Throughout history, this genetic commonality has provided an invaluable tool to enhance human survival. Common hereditary traits provide critical understanding of an extended family's physical and mental strengths, weaknesses, and susceptibility to disease and death. Even before the advent of modern science, this information was collectively shared among extended family members and served to alert and prepare them for eventualities related to the onset of disease and other life patterns, thus strengthening their health and livelihood. Modern medical technologies have only increased this capability, as research of an extended family's genetics now serves to predict, detect, and treat common, family-related diseases, further enhancing human survival.

¶ 27 Upon extended families are built people groups or ethnic groups of individual races, tribes, kindred, and nationalities based upon their broadly shared genetic characteristics. In addition to developing understanding about their mutually shared health risks, people groups throughout history have looked outward to their physical surroundings and, based upon their common genetics and collective experiences, have obtained the knowledge necessary for their people to adapt to and function well in the physical environment, thus enhancing their health and longevity. People groups around the world have been linked to make up the larger human race. While world customs and cultures vary greatly, these societies share the common foundational element of a woman and a man united in marriage. It is little wonder the Supreme Court has said that marriage is “fundamental to the very existence and survival of the race.” Zablocki, 434 U.S. at 384, 98 S.Ct. 673 (citing Skinner, 316 U.S. at 541, 62 S.Ct. 1110). One court well summed up these principles: “[T]he State has a compelling interest in fostering the traditional institution of marriage (whether based on self-preservation, procreation, or in nurturing and keeping alive the concept of marriage and family as a basic fabric of our society), as old and as fundamental as our entire civilization, which institution is deeply rooted and long established in firm and rich societal values.” In re Estate of Cooper, 149 Misc.2d 282, 564 N.Y.S.2d 684, 688 (N.Y.Surrog.Ct.1990); see also Conaway, 932 A.2d at 630 (“In light of the fundamental nature of procreation, and the importance placed on it by the Supreme Court, safeguarding an environment most conducive to the stable propagation and continuance of the human race is a legitimate government interest.”).

¶ 28 These principles demonstrate clearly that marriage is not merely a private act. It is also a public act which serves a public function critical to society, that of bringing together female and male to create and raise the future generation. Courts have recognized this, holding that the above-discussed critical societal functions are uniquely provided by marriage between a woman and man and cannot be replicated by other relationships.

“Because only relationships between opposite-sex couples can naturally produce children, it is reasonable for the state to afford unique legal recognition to that particular social unit in the form of opposite-sex marriage. The legislature could reasonably conclude that the institution of civil marriage as it has existed in the country from the beginning has successfully provided this desirable social structure and should be preserved.” In re J.B., 326 S.W.3d 654, 677 (Tex.App.Dallas 2010) (internal citations omitted). “Indisputably, the only sexual relationship capable of producing children is one between a man and a woman. The State could reasonably decide that by encouraging opposite-sex couples to marry, thereby assuming legal and financial obligations, the children born from such relationships will have better opportunities to be nurtured and raised by two parents within long-term, committed relationships, which society has traditionally viewed as advantageous for children. Because same-sex couples cannot by themselves procreate, the State could also reasonably decide that sanctioning same-sex marriages would do little to advance the State's interest in ensuring responsible procreation within committed, long-term relationships.Standhardt v. Super. Ct. of Ariz., 206 Ariz. 276, 77 P.3d 451, 462–63, ¶ 38 (App. Div. 1 2003) (emphasis added); see also Citizens for Equal Protec. v. Bruning, 455 F.3d 859, 868 (8th Cir.2006) (“[Appellees'] argument disregards the expressed intent of traditional marriage laws—to encourage heterosexual couples to bear and raise children in committed marriage relationships.”).

Because this case does not involve an equal protection challenge as between married and unmarried heterosexual couples, I do not here focus on or develop an analysis regarding the distinctions between them.

“[S]o far as heterosexuals are concerned, the evidence that on average married couples live longer, are healthier, earn more, have lower rates of substance abuse and mental illness, are less likely to commit suicide, and report higher levels of happiness—that marriage civilizes young males, confers economies of scale and of joint consumption, minimizes sexually transmitted disease, and provides a stable and nourishing framework for child rearing—refutes any claim that policies designed to promote marriage are irrational.” Irizarry v. Bd. of Educ. of Chicago, 251 F.3d 604, 607 (7th Cir.2001) (citations omitted). Modern medicine makes it technologically possible for some same-sex couples to artificially conceive and bear children. However, that fact does not diminish the truth that human life cannot be sustained without procreative marriage relationships, even in light of modern technology.

While not all heterosexual couples have the ability or desire to procreate and raise children, the jurisprudence is premised upon the potential of producing children which lies within the marriage structure and the state's interest, as stated here, in “encourag[ing]” these outcomes. Citizens for Equal Protec., 455 F.3d at 868. “The fundamental right to marriage and its ensuing benefits are conferred on opposite-sex couples not because of a distinction between whether various opposite-sex couples actually procreate, but rather because of the possibility of procreation.” Conaway, 932 A.2d at 633.

¶ 29 Consequently, the right to marry has not been held to mean there is a fundamental right to marry someone of the same gender. “[V]irtually every court to have considered the issue has held that same-sex marriage is not constitutionally protected as fundamental in either their state or the Nation as a whole.” Conaway, 932 A.2d at 628 (citations omitted). “The idea that same-sex marriage is even possible is a relatively new one. Until a few decades ago, it was an accepted truth for almost everyone who ever lived, in any society in which marriage existed, that there could be marriages only between participants of different sex.... The right to marry is unquestionably a fundamental right. The right to marry someone of the same sex, however, is not ‘deeply rooted’; it has not even been asserted until relatively recent times.” Hernandez v. Robles, 7 N.Y.3d 338, 821 N.Y.S.2d 770, 855 N.E.2d 1, 8–9 (2006) (citations omitted).

In Baker, 291 Minn. 310, 191 N.W.2d 185, the Minnesota Supreme Court held that a state statute, interpreted by the Court as not authorizing same-sex marriages, did not violate due process or equal protection. The U.S. Supreme Court dismissed the subsequent appeal for “want of [a] substantial federal question.” 409 U.S. at 810, 93 S.Ct. 37. The U.S. Supreme Court's action in Baker has been described as binding precedent. Andersen v. King Co., 158 Wash.2d 1, 138 P.3d 963, 999 (2006) (citing to Baker and holding “the same-sex union as a constitutional right argument was so frivolous as to merit dismissal without further argument by the Supreme Court. A similar result is required today.”); Morrison v. Sadler, 821 N.E.2d 15, 19 (Ind.App.2005) (citing to Baker and stating: “There is binding United States Supreme Court precedent indicating that state bans on same-sex marriage do not violate the United States Constitution.”); Wilson v. Ake, 354 F.Supp.2d 1298, 1305 (M.D.Fla.2005) (“Baker v. Nelson is binding precedent upon this Court”); but see In re Kandu, 315 B.R. 123, 138 (W.D.Wash.2004); In re J.B., 326 S.W.3d 654, 672 (Tex.App.Dallas 2010).

¶ 30 Given this exclusive importance of marriage, the law developed to give it sanction, permanence, and a formal structure upon which to base legal entitlement and obligation. Although commonly referred to as a contractual relationship, the obligation of marriage is more than merely contractual. As the Supreme Court has explained, “when the contract to marry is executed by the marriage, a relation between the parties is created which they cannot change. Other contracts may be modified, restricted, or enlarged, or entirely released upon the consent of the parties. Not so with marriage. The relation once formed, the law steps in and holds the parties to various obligations and liabilities.” Maynard, 125 U.S. at 210–11, 8 S.Ct. at 729. “When the contracting parties have entered into the married state, they have not so much entered into a contract as into a new relation, the rights, duties and obligations of which rest, not upon their agreement, but upon the general law of the State, statutory or common, which defines and prescribes those rights, duties and obligations. They are of law, not of contract.” Adams, 51 Me. at 483. As we have noted, “it is to the interest of the state that [marriage] be permanent.” Franklin, 40 Mont. at 350, 106 P. at 354.

¶ 31 Upon this structure of permanence, and again in view of the exclusive importance of marriage, the state has built a system of exclusive benefits and protections on behalf of, and dependent upon, marriage. “[M]arital status often is a pre-condition to the receipt of government benefits ( e.g., Social Security benefits), property rights ( e.g., tenancy by the entirety, inheritance rights), and other, less tangible benefits ( e.g., legitimation of children born out of wedlock).” Turner, 482 U.S. at 96, 107 S.Ct. at 2265. “In terms of federal benefits, the Government Accounting Office (GAO) compiled in 1997, and updated in 2004, a list of federal rights, responsibilities, and privileges granted to married couples, but denied to same-sex couples. According to the study, there were 1,138 federal statutes providing such benefits.” Conaway, 932 A.2d at 582 n. 6 (citations omitted). Plaintiffs provided the District Court with a list of over 340 Montana statutes that classify based on marital status and that would be impacted by the proposed relief sought.

¶ 32 While Plaintiffs do not claim the right to marry, they are nonetheless claiming constitutional entitlement to all of these same rights and benefits which are provided to married couples on the ground that they are “similarly situated in every material respect.” However, this position ignores the historical and long-developed legal foundation and formal structure giving marriage an exclusive legal permanence, which does not exist for other relationships. More importantly, the above discussion, including the precedent addressing marriage and its unique attributes, demonstrates that Plaintiffs' claim to be “similarly situated” to married couples is without merit. This is not meant to disparage Plaintiffs or minimize the contributions they offer, but is simply a statement of the reality that marriage between a woman and man exclusively provides unique and transcendent societal protections vital to human survival which differentiate it and make it dissimilar from other relationships. These protections uniquely provided by marriage form a legitimate and even compelling state interest, and thus a constitutional basis, for the State's exclusive treatment of marriage.

¶ 33 The above discussion of the law of marriage reflects the general state of the law before the Marriage Amendment was adopted by Montanans in 2004. Although some of the cited cases were decided after adoption of the Marriage Amendment, they were premised upon pre–2004 precedent, and marriage was considered to be a fundamental right with constitutionally protected status at the time of the Amendment's adoption. However, several years earlier, legal arguments attacking the exclusive status of marriage began to be offered, and considerable concern was generated over whether the law's exclusive treatment of marriage would remain, or whether courts would begin to overturn long-standing precedent favoring marriage. With all due respect, several courts indicated a willingness to uproot established legal precedent recognizing the uniqueness of marriage between a man and woman, and eliminate the law's exclusive treatment of marriage. See e.g. Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 852 P.2d 44 (1993); Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 744 A.2d 864 (2000); Goodridge v. Dept. of Pub. Health, 440 Mass. 309, 798 N.E.2d 941 (2003).

¶ 34 The response of the citizens of the country to these court decisions can only be described as a phenomenon of direct democracy. To counter this threat to established precedent favoring marriage, citizens of some 31 states acted to either reinstate the law's exclusive definition and treatment of marriage in some manner, or to ensure that courts could not eliminate such exclusive treatment, by amending their state constitutions to explicitly protect marriage. Montana was one of those states.

¶ 35 Building on the foundation of historical legal protections for marriage, Montana voters solidified the premise that marriage is between one man and one woman by placing the concept expressly into the Montana Constitution. Mont. Const. art. XIII, § 7. The Voter Information Packet provided voters with the arguments for and against adoption of the Amendment. Proponents stated that the “[t]he time-honored, vital institution of marriage is being threatened.... Special interest groups are constantly seeking to gain special rights that infringe on the rights of the rest of society. Such special rights cost all Montanans.... Voting yes on CI–96 allows the people to give clear direction to judges on this important issue.”

¶ 36 Directly related to this case, proponents discussed the issue of benefits which are attendant to marriage. “If CI–96 fails, how will homosexual marriage one day affect your family? ... Small business employers in Montana may someday be required to provide expanded health coverage, retirement and fringe benefits to same-sex ‘spouses' of employees. The broad subjectivity of such un-funded mandates could hurt Montana's economy and jobs.” Opponents likewise also focused on benefits and obligations associated with same-sex couples: “if CI–96 were to pass, the State could nullify the contractual agreements made between same-gender partners. CI–96 would limit innovative and robust companies from treating their employees equitably.” As the District Court noted, both sides of the debate acknowledged “that the marriage amendment would have something to do with the benefits and obligations that relate to the status of being married.”

¶ 37 Proponents and opponents alike focused on the issue of benefits because everyone understood the law: that marriage is a concrete legal status upon which the State premises exclusive treatment and benefits, as demonstrated by the above-cited authority. It is more than a label, a societal choice, a union of two people, or an aspiration. Indeed, marriage is an obligation given exclusive protections in the law because it provides exclusive protections to society. Even before adoption of the Marriage Amendment, this was recognized in Montana statute. See e.g. §§ 40–1–101, 40–1–103, 40–1–401, 40–2–101, 40–2–102, MCA. Montana has long used marital status as an exclusive basis for provision and allotment of benefits and obligations. See e.g. §§ 2–18–601, 19–17–405, 33–22–140, 39–51–2205, 39–71–723, 50–9–106, 72–2–112, 15–30–2114, 15–30–2366, MCA. Building on these statutory provisions and the prior holdings of our cases, Montana citizens enacted the Marriage Amendment to expressly “constitutionalize” these principles, thereby strengthening the law's exclusive treatment of marriage. See State v. Toomey, 135 Mont. 35, 51–53, 335 P.2d 1051, 1059–60 (1958) ( “[W]e must construe the amendment in the light of the conditions as they existed at the time of its adoption.” Rankin v. Love, 125 Mont. 184, 187, 232 P.2d 998, 1000 (1951); State ex rel. Bottomly v. District Court, 73 Mont. 541, 547, 237 P. 525, 527 (1925).... “It is only reasonable to assume that the people, in adopting the amendment to our Constitution, adopted it in light of the existing [state law] and the construction placed upon that law by this Court.”).

¶ 38 When asked during oral argument what unique legal concreteness would remain to marriage if the requested relief was granted, Plaintiffs' counsel replied, “How people view it, how symbolic and how important and how solemn it is, is important. Marriage is meaningful.” When asked again, “In what way? I'm trying to understand what concrete[ness] in the law is left?” Counsel responded, “The significance is that you're married.” However, such a diminished concept of marriage would necessitate a dramatic rewriting of the law. Marriage has always been much more—a concrete legal status which the law recognized and favored with exclusive treatment, including benefits and obligations. In adopting the Marriage Amendment, Montana voters determined to permanently preserve this exclusive treatment for marriage by placing it in the Constitution. Thus, in one way, Plaintiffs are asking this Court to render the Marriage Amendment superfluous by holding that it added nothing to the law's previous exclusive classification of marriage.

But further, Plaintiffs are asking the Court to hold the Marriage Amendment actually had a reverse effect—that marriage has less legal protection now than before the Amendment was passed, because marriage can no longer serve as the basis for exclusive treatment by the State. Clearly, this is directly contrary to the “clear direction to judges” which the Marriage Amendment was designed to give.

In addition to the above-cited legal rulings, marriage was limited to a man and woman under prior statutory law. See§§ 40–1–401(1)(d), 40–1–103, MCA.

¶ 39 “The Equal Protection Clause ‘is not a license for courts to judge the wisdom, fairness, or logic of [the voters'] choices.’ ” Citizens for Equal Protec., 455 F.3d at 867 (bracket in original) (quoting F.C.C. v. Beach Commun., Inc., 508 U.S. 307, 313, 113 S.Ct. 2096, 2101, 124 L.Ed.2d 211 (1993)). Now that the marriage relationship has been given constitutionally-protected status, any change to the long-standing principles which govern this issue must come from the people through the democratic process, not from the courts.

“The package of government benefits and restrictions that accompany the institution of formal marriage serve a variety of other purposes. The legislature—or the people through the initiative process—may rationally choose not to expand in wholesale fashion the groups entitled to those benefits.” Citizens for Equal Protec., 455 F.3d at 868 (emphasis added). “[A]s we have explained, there is no fundamental right to be free of the political barrier a validly enacted constitutional amendment erects.” Citizens for Equal Protec., 455 F.3d at 868.

Several of the cases cited herein were followed by democratic initiatives to grant rights to same-sex couples.

¶ 40 I appreciate the deeply-held feelings and beliefs of the Plaintiffs and condemn any acts of cruelty they have suffered, some of which are referenced in their affidavits. Yet, given the long-standing legal protections and exclusive treatment of marriage, with its corresponding benefits and obligations, and the incorporation of those principles into the Montana Constitution by the citizens of Montana, Plaintiffs' equal protection claim must fail.

¶ 41 I concur.

Justice PATRICIA O. COTTER dissents.

¶ 42 I dissent from the Court's Opinion, and concur with virtually all of Justice Nelson's well-written and comprehensive Dissent. I write separately to state that I would not liken the Court's approach here to cases sanctioning slavery and racial segregation. Dissent, ¶ 51. Moreover, I do not agree that the Court is taking the approach it has adopted “to avoid a socially divisive issue.” Dissent, ¶ 74. Although I disagree with the Court's analysis and resolution, I do not believe it is acting in bad faith.

¶ 43 Second, I decline to join the bulk of Part V of the Dissent, which challenges the constitutionality of the Marriage Amendment. Plaintiffs do not challenge the Marriage Amendment, and I agree that the relief Plaintiffs seek does not offend the Marriage Amendment in the slightest.

¶ 44 With the foregoing caveat, I therefore join Justice Nelson's Dissent through the first sentence of ¶ 179.

Justice MICHAEL E. WHEAT joins the Dissent of Justice PATRICIA O. COTTER.



Justice JAMES C. NELSON, dissenting.

I. INTRODUCTION

¶ 45 [I]f we have learned anything from the significant evolution in the prevailing societal views and official policies toward members of minority races and toward women over the past half-century, it is that even the most familiar and generally accepted of social practices and traditions often mask an unfairness and inequality that frequently is not recognized or appreciated by those not directly harmed by those practices or traditions.


In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757, 76 Cal.Rptr.3d 683, 183 P.3d 384, 451 (2008).

¶ 46 There are some cases where we look back and can see that the court was clearly on the wrong side of history. Among the most notorious are Dred Scott v. Sanford, 60 U.S. 393, 19 How. 393, 15 L.Ed. 691 (1857) (slaves of African descent are property, not citizens); Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 16 S.Ct. 1138, 41 L.Ed. 256 (1896) (segregation of white and colored people in public facilities does not violate equal protection, provided the facilities are “equal”); Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412, 421–23, 28 S.Ct. 324, 326–27, 52 L.Ed. 551 (1908) (differential treatment of women in employment is justified because “woman has always been dependent upon man”); Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S. 200, 47 S.Ct. 584, 71 L.Ed. 1000 (1927) (compulsory sterilization of feebleminded individuals “in order to prevent our being swamped with incompetence” does not violate due process or equal protection; “[t]hree generations of imbeciles are enough”); People v. Hall, 4 Cal. 399, 404–05 (Cal.1854) (the Chinese, being “a race of people whom nature has marked as inferior” and who are “incapable of progress or intellectual development beyond a certain point,” may be precluded from testifying against white persons); and Scott v. State, 39 Ga. 321, 323 (1869) (racial intermarriage is “unnatural” and “productive of deplorable results”; “the offspring of these unnatural connections are generally sickly and effeminate”). I venture to say that another case belonging on this list is Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 106 S.Ct. 2841, 92 L.Ed.2d 140 (1986) (the state may regulate private sexual conduct between consenting adults), which the Supreme Court overruled in Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 123 S.Ct. 2472, 156 L.Ed.2d 508 (2003) (individual decisions by two adults—married or unmarried—concerning the intimacies of their physical relationship are a form of “liberty” protected by the Fourteenth Amendment). As Justice Kennedy aptly stated in his opinion for the Court in Lawrence, “times can blind us to certain truths and later generations can see that laws once thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to oppress.” 539 U.S. at 579, 123 S.Ct. at 2484.

¶ 47 In the wake of the Hawaii Supreme Court's decision in Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 852 P.2d 44 (1993), which held that denying same-sex couples the ability to marry must be justified under “strict scrutiny” principles, measures were proposed and adopted in as many as 30 states, including Montana, purporting to limit marriage to one man and one woman. Due to the success of these measures, it became “a constant theme of opponents of same-sex marriage that whenever it has been put before the voters it has lost.” Erik Eckholm, In Maine and Maryland, Victories at the Ballot Box for Same–Sex Marriage, N.Y. Times (Nov. 7, 2012). That, however, is no longer true. In this most recent election of November 6, 2012, voters in Maine, Maryland, and Washington approved ballot measures authorizing same-sex couples to marry. And in Minnesota, voters defeated a ballot measure that would have amended the Minnesota Constitution to limit marriage to one man and one woman. It appears that a majority of voters in these states have seen through the scare tactics and propaganda which “family values” organizations and certain religious groups have used to persuade the electorate that allowing same-sex marriage will harm children, hurt businesses and the economy, intrude on religious freedoms, and undermine the institution of marriage itself. As discussed in greater detail later in this Dissent, there is no actual evidence supporting any of the maledictions and stereotypes used in the campaigns against same-sex marriage.

¶ 48 Meanwhile, in Montana, the issue at hand is not about same-sex marriage. It is less dramatic, though by no means less important. It concerns the right of committed intimate same-sex couples to receive the same civil protections which the State makes available to committed intimate different-sex couples. Plaintiffs assert, and rightly so, that their government may not single out unpopular groups for disfavored treatment, as the State of Montana has done here. Shockingly, this Court refuses to uphold this most basic principle of constitutional law. While I have not always agreed with this Court's decisions—in fact, I have strenuously disagreed with my colleagues on occasion

—I have never disagreed more strongly with the Court as I do in this case. With due respect, I believe today's decision, like those mentioned above, wrongly deprives an abused minority of their civil rights.

See e.g. Western Tradition Partn. v. Atty. Gen., 2011 MT 328, ¶¶ 61–135, 363 Mont. 220, 271 P.3d 1 (dissent); Musselshell Ranch Co. v. Seidel–Joukova, 2011 MT 217, ¶¶ 36–86, 362 Mont. 1, 261 P.3d 570 (partial dissent); Rohlfs v. Klemenhagen, LLC, 2009 MT 440, ¶¶ 47–118, 354 Mont. 133, 227 P.3d 42 (dissent); Gonzales v. City of Bozeman, 2009 MT 277, ¶¶ 54–87, 352 Mont. 145, 217 P.3d 487 (dissent); Kafka v. Mont. Dept. of Fish, Wildlife and Parks, 2008 MT 460, ¶¶ 96–248, 348 Mont. 80, 201 P.3d 8 (dissent); Nelson v. State, 2008 MT 336, ¶¶ 64–78, 346 Mont. 206, 195 P.3d 293 (partial dissent); Confederated Salish and Kootenai Tribes v. Clinch, 2007 MT 63, ¶¶ 46–158, 336 Mont. 302, 158 P.3d 377 (dissent); State v. Mizenko, 2006 MT 11, ¶¶ 44–192, 330 Mont. 299, 127 P.3d 458 (dissent); Goldstein v. Commn. on Prac. of the Sup.Ct., 2000 MT 8, ¶¶ 52–124, 297 Mont. 493, 995 P.2d 923 (dissent); Durden v. Hydro Flame Corp., 1999 MT 186, ¶¶ 33–58, 295 Mont. 318, 983 P.2d 943 (dissent); State v. Guillaume, 1999 MT 29, ¶¶ 32–42, 293 Mont. 224, 975 P.2d 312 (dissent).

¶ 49 This Dissent is lengthy. It is meant to be, for several reasons. First, I believe this is the most important civil rights case to come before this Court in decades. And it will be my last opportunity, sitting as a member of this Court, to address the fundamental constitutional rights of gay, lesbian, and bisexual people and the discrimination which the State of Montana is perpetrating against these individuals. The issues here are significant and complex, and deserving of thorough consideration, analysis, and discussion.

¶ 50 Second, I am profoundly disappointed in this Court, as an institution, for rendering a decision that requires Plaintiffs, the same-sex couples here, to wage a litigation jihad against their own government to obtain the statutory rights, benefits, and protections to which they are constitutionally entitled. I have located no court decision in this country—state or federal—applying the declaratory judgment laws in the cabined and unworkable fashion that this Court does here.

¶ 51 Lastly, I am thoroughly disheartened that today's decision takes civil rights in this State backward to a time when court decisions supported and facilitated other equally pernicious forms of government-sanctioned discrimination, including slavery and racial segregation; women being viewed as little more than men's dependents, unable to vote or own property; the Chinese being deemed an “inferior” race; the compulsory sterilization of the “feebleminded”; and the criminalization of private sexual intimacy between two consenting adults. No other minority group has been treated in this fashion in this State in modern times. This, truly, is a shameful, black day for civil rights in Montana.

¶ 52 Yet, while gay, lesbian, and bisexual citizens may have lost this battle, the war is not over. If we have learned anything as an evolving species, it is that no government, no religion, no institution, and no political party can long oppress the inviolable dignity and spirit of human beings in their fight for fairness in the courts, access to justice, and equal protection of the laws.

¶ 53 With these introductory remarks, I now proceed to my detailed discussion and analysis. In Part II (¶¶ 57–80), I provide a background and overview of the case and the issues. In Part III (¶¶ 81–113), I explain the declaratory judgment laws and address in detail the District Court's and this Court's erroneous analyses under those laws.

¶ 54 Next, in Part IV (¶¶ 114–168), I analyze Plaintiffs' constitutional claim. Given the evidence that gay, lesbian, and bisexual people are reviled and demonized in Montana and have suffered a history of invidious and prejudicial treatment, I conclude that sexual orientation is a suspect class under Montana's Equal Protection Clause, and thus that discrimination based on sexual orientation in the provision of statutory benefits, protections, and services must survive “strict scrutiny” review. I further conclude that treating Plaintiffs differently based on sexual orientation is an affront to and violation of their inviolable right to human dignity, also protected by Montana's Constitution.

¶ 55 As a final matter, in Part V (¶¶ 169–206), I am compelled to address the so-called Marriage Amendment to Montana's Constitution (Mont. Const. art. XIII, § 7). Plaintiffs do not ask to be “married,” and granting them the relief they seek does not offend that provision in the slightest. Yet, the State relies on the Marriage Amendment as support for its position, and the State's argument before this Court is bolstered by an outpouring of attacks on the same-sex couples by no less than 128 Montana protestant churches and the Montana Catholic Bishops, all appearing through the Montana Catholic Conference as amicus curiae, along with other “family values” organizations, also appearing as amici curiae. The Marriage Amendment is the conduit through which the State and its amici claim that it may deprive Plaintiffs—who, because of this provision, cannot marry—of the statutory benefits and protections which the State grants to married couples. That the State and its amici have injected the Marriage Amendment into this case at all, however, demonstrates, in spades, what that provision is really about: the constitutionalization of religious doctrine. Indeed, what the State and its amici seek to do here is conflate sectarian canons regarding marriage with secular laws governing the provision of benefits and protections to committed couples. In my view, this approach violates several constitutional provisions, not the least of which is the clause in Montana's Declaration of Rights prohibiting the State from establishing religion. Emblematic of the religiously grounded discrimination defended by the State and its amici is the blatant mendacity underlying the Marriage Amendment initiative—a fourberie reminiscent of some of the worst propaganda campaigns perpetrated in modern times.

¶ 56 In the last section of this Dissent, Part VI (¶¶ 207–212), I set forth my conclusions and provide a short epilogue.

II. BACKGROUND AND OVERVIEW

¶ 57 Plaintiffs here are twelve lesbian, gay, or bisexual individuals who are in six committed, intimate, same-sex relationships. As of the filing of their affidavits in the District Court on December 10, 2010, plaintiffs Donaldson and Guggenheim had been in a relationship for 27 years; Leslie and Haugland for 12 years; Stallings and Wagner for 21 years; Gibson and Boettcher for 11 years; Long and Parker for 8 years; and Owens and Williams for 18 years. With their life partners, Plaintiffs have established families which provide them with long-term mutual emotional and economic support and a stable environment for raising children. Plaintiffs are employed in, or have retired from, a variety of professions including teaching, coaching, counseling, engineering, music, art, and medicine. They are active in their children's schools, in their churches, in their professions, and in their communities. One has served in the Montana Legislature. It is undisputed that Plaintiffs are productive members of society and have, in fact, successfully raised a number of children. Some Plaintiffs are now grandparents.

¶ 58 Plaintiffs desire to protect their family relationships in the same way their heterosexual neighbors, coworkers, and fellow community members are able to do under Montana law. Plaintiffs have taken some steps in this regard. For example, they have entered into joint tenancy arrangements on their houses and bank accounts and have executed powers of attorney, healthcare directives, and wills in favor of their partners. Plaintiffs point out, however, that such private legal arrangements can be expensive and, thus, are not available to many couples. Plaintiffs also express concerns about whether these arrangements will be honored—especially in the event of a medical emergency. Some Plaintiffs describe (in their affidavits) past incidents when healthcare personnel refused to speak with them about their partner's condition. Another Plaintiff (Leslie) describes how she and her former partner, Erika, took many of the legally available steps to protect their relationship. Yet, after Erika died in a work-related accident on Christmas Day 1996, which was their eighth anniversary, Leslie found herself “powerless and degraded” and treated like a “legal stranger” when she attempted to exercise the responsibilities of a partner. She was denied access to Erika's remains; she was denied a copy of the death certificate by the sheriff because she was a “stranger in blood”; she was refused paid bereavement leave by her employer (the same employer for whom Erika had been working when she was killed) and thus had to go back to work only a week after Erika's death; she had no rights under the intestacy laws with regard to Erika's property; she had no legal means to prevent Erika's family from entering their home, going through their belongings, and taking Erika's possessions, many of which the two had shared as domestic partners; and, to add insult to injury, she was required to pay inheritance taxes on the proceeds from Erika's half of their condominium, which Leslie was forced to sell.

¶ 59 The underlying issue, as the District Court stated in its Order, is that “individuals such as Plaintiffs are denied a variety of benefits and protections that are statutorily available to heterosexual spouses.” The District Court identified some of these statutes and noted some of the “real life scenarios” in which these laws have affected Plaintiffs. For example, Montana's intestacy laws and workers' compensation laws provide certain protections to the surviving spouse of a different-sex relationship, but not to the surviving partner of a same-sex relationship. Likewise, bereavement leave is made available to a different-sex spouse but not to a same-sex partner. Furthermore, Plaintiffs are unable under Montana's tax laws to file joint returns or to take the spousal exemption for nonworking spouses if filing separately. Montana law permits the different-sex spouse of a terminally ill person to withhold life-sustaining treatment, but does not afford this right to the same-sex partner of a terminally ill person. Similarly, the different-sex spouse of a person who has become mentally incompetent has priority to become guardian, but a same-sex partner does not have this same right.

¶ 60 If not for the fact that each couple consists of two members of the same sex, Plaintiffs' relationships could qualify as “marriage” under Montana law. Title 40, chapter 1, MCA. As noted, however, Plaintiffs do not ask to be granted the status of “married.” For purposes of this case, Plaintiffs only seek a determination that they are entitled, as a matter of constitutional law, to obtain the same rights and benefits—along with the same mutual responsibilities and obligations—which the State of Montana has chosen to grant to different-sex married couples. The premise underlying this claim is that “marriage” does not include an exclusive right to any particular rights and benefits conferred by the government, and that “marriage” connotes something other than just the receipt of such rights and benefits. See e.g. In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757, 76 Cal.Rptr.3d 683, 183 P.3d 384, 426–27, 434–35, 444–46 (C2008) (“the constitutional right to marry clearly does not obligate the state to afford specific tax or other governmental benefits on the basis of a couple's family relationship”; even if all of the personal and dignity interests which have traditionally informed the right to marry have been given to same-sex couples through the Domestic Partner Act, there is still “a considerable and undeniable symbolic importance” to the designation of “marriage”); Kerrigan v. Commr. of Pub. Health, 289 Conn. 135, 957 A.2d 407, 417–18 (2008) (“[m]arriage ... is not merely shorthand for a discrete set of legal rights and responsibilities”; “[a]lthough marriage and civil unions do embody the same legal rights under our law, they are by no means ‘equal’ [;] ... the former is an institution of transcendent historical, cultural and social significance, whereas the latter most surely is not”); Perry v. Brown, 671 F.3d 1052, 1077–79 (9th Cir.2012) (discussing “the extraordinary significance of the official designation of ‘marriage’ ” apart from the rights, protections, and benefits conferred by the government). Therefore, Plaintiffs argue, when the State chooses to make benefits and protections available to persons in committed intimate relationships, the State must do so evenhandedly, without discriminating on the basis of the sexual orientation of the persons in those relationships. In a sense, Plaintiffs are merely demanding “separate but equal” treatment by the State—the minimal floor of equal protection rights under Plessy.

¶ 61 The Attorney General does not deny that the State could provide such protections to committed intimate same-sex couples. As a matter of fact, the Attorney General acknowledges in his appellate brief that “the Legislature could choose to provide benefits similar to spousal benefits to unmarried couples” and that “the Legislature could create a different status conferring similar benefits outside of marriage for civil unions or domestic partners.” The Attorney General, speaking through an Assistant Attorney General, made similar statements during oral argument.

¶ 62 One may wonder, then, why we do not simply grant Plaintiffs the declaratory relief they seek. While I certainly do not condone the “separate but equal” doctrine of Plessy—which the Supreme Court overruled in Brown v. Board of Ed., 347 U.S. 483, 74 S.Ct. 686, 98 L.Ed. 873 (1954)—Plaintiffs have made clear that, for purposes of this lawsuit, they do not seek the status of marriage. They merely seek “equal opportunity” to obtain the same benefits and protections which the State, in its discretion, has chosen to make available to different-sex couples. It is surely beyond cavil that Plaintiffs are entitled, at the very least, to the equal protection of these laws—even if that protection is effected through a regime that does not include marriage, as the Attorney General suggests. See Alaska Civ. Liberties Union v. State, 122 P.3d 781, 793–94 (Alaska 2005) (restricting public benefits programs to different-sex married couples violates the rights of employees with same-sex partners to “equal rights, opportunities, and protection under the law”); Lewis v. Harris, 188 N.J. 415, 908 A.2d 196, 220–21 (2006) (as a matter of equal protection, “committed same-sex couples must be afforded on equal terms the same rights and benefits enjoyed by married opposite-sex couples”); Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 744 A.2d 864, 886 (1999) (the State has “a constitutional obligation to extend to [same-sex couples] the common benefit, protection, and security that Vermont law provides opposite-sex married couples”).

¶ 63 It appears from the District Court record, the arguments on appeal, and the Court's Opinion that the hindrance in recognizing and declaring these rights boils down to a simple refusal by those in power to make the constitutionally sound—albeit politically unpopular—decision. For starters, rather than concede the elementary premise of this lawsuit—that it is a denial of equal protection to make statutory protections available to different-sex couples, who may obtain them by getting married, but to categorically deny them to same-sex couples, who are not able to get married—the Attorney General instead attempts to justify and prolong this institutionalized discrimination being perpetrated by the State of Montana against a discrete minority of its citizens.

Frankly, the State's arguments in this regard are inconsistent and difficult to follow. On one hand, the State concedes that the Legislature could provide committed intimate same-sex couples with similar benefits as are afforded to different-sex married couples. Yet, on the other hand, the State suggests that any benefits provided to different-sex married couples cannot also be provided to same-sex couples due to the Marriage Amendment. This reasoning is clearly a non sequitur for reasons discussed in greater detail in the Marriage Amendment section below. See ¶¶ 174–179, infra. For the time being, it suffices to point out that the Marriage Amendment merely states: “Only a marriage between one man and one woman shall be valid or recognized as a marriage in this state.” And, as noted, Plaintiffs are not asking that their relationships be recognized as “marriage.” Furthermore, the Marriage Amendment does not require the State to grant married couples tax benefits, or the right to make medical decisions for a spouse, or the right to death benefits under the workers' compensation laws, etc. Nor does it say that these sorts of benefits and protections, if the State chooses to grant them, may not also be offered to unmarried persons. The State concedes that the Legislature could enact a civil-union or domestic-partnership scheme.

In contrast, see e.g. Perry v. Brown, 52 Cal.4th 1116, 134 Cal.Rptr.3d 499, 265 P.3d 1002, 1008 (2011): “The answer filed by the [California] Attorney General also declined to defend the initiative, but went further and affirmatively took the position that Proposition 8 [which amended the California Constitution to prohibit same-sex marriage] is unconstitutional.” See also e.g. Ltr. from Eric H. Holder Jr., U.S. Atty. Gen., to John A. Boehner, Speaker, U.S. H.R., at 2 (Feb. 23, 2011) (Dkt. 42 in the District Court record): “[T]he President [of the United States] and I have concluded that classifications based on sexual orientation warrant heightened scrutiny and that, as applied to same-sex couples legally married under state law, Section 3 of [the Defense of Marriage Act] is unconstitutional.”

¶ 64 Perhaps for these reasons, the State ultimately takes the position that Plaintiffs' constitutional claim should not be decided at all. The reason: a ruling in Plaintiffs' favor could result in the invalidation of “innumerable” unspecified statutes. Yet, surely the fact that Plaintiffs are being discriminated against in “innumerable” ways is reason to hasten a decision on the merits of their claim, not delay it. Regrettably, however, a majority of this Court defers to the Attorney General's approach. Instead of requiring the State to demonstrate the constitutionality of its practices, the Court punts. The Court implies that Plaintiffs are to blame—that their failure to “specifically identify” and “specifically analyze” the “specific statutes” that are discriminatory somehow precludes us from declaring Plaintiffs' rights. Opinion, ¶¶ 9, 11, 13. How the Court expects Plaintiffs to present their claim is not entirely clear from the Court's opaque analysis. But a careful inspection reveals the Court's rationale to be entirely disingenuous in any event.

¶ 65 First of all, Plaintiffs have identified numerous statutes which grant benefits and protections to different-sex spouses but not to same-sex partners. Indeed, after observing in its Order that “Plaintiffs are denied a variety of benefits and protections that are statutorily available to heterosexual spouses,” the District Court lists a slew of those statutes. Furthermore, Plaintiffs attached a laundry list of the discriminatory statutes to their motion to alter or amend the judgment. That list is attached as Appendix 1 to this Dissent. If what the Court needs is a specific statute to analyze, the Court can simply pick one of the numerous statutes identified in the District Court's Order or in Plaintiffs' list, and assess its validity in light of the parties' arguments. The constitutional principles of the Court's analysis could then be extrapolated and applied to other statutes.

¶ 66 Secondly, if the Court is suggesting that Plaintiffs may not obtain a declaratory ruling until they have specifically identified every single discriminatory statute, it appears entirely likely that the extensive list of statutes attached to Plaintiffs' motion to alter or amend the judgment is, in fact, a listing of every single discriminatory statute. If that is what the Court needs, then the Court need look no further than Plaintiffs' motion, which is contained in the District Court record. More importantly, however, the Court has cited no authority whatsoever for requiring Plaintiffs to identify all of the discriminatory statutes. In fact, as I discuss in further detail below, the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act enables Plaintiffs to obtain a declaration of their rights in a single lawsuit, without necessarily identifying each and every discriminatory statute.

¶ 67 Thirdly, if the Court is suggesting that Plaintiffs must challenge each statute on an individual basis, the Court has cited no authority for this approach either. Indeed, one purpose of the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act is to avoid such seriatim litigation. As Plaintiffs reminded the District Court in their motion to alter or amend the judgment, they sought declaratory relief “in part to avoid this type of expensive and protracted litigation that would drain judicial resources while prolonging the harm experienced by Plaintiffs and their families.” Cf. McGillivray v. State, 1999 MT 3, ¶¶ 9–11, 293 Mont. 19, 972 P.2d 804 (concluding that declaratory relief was the only “reasonable remedy” where, absent such relief, only those plaintiffs who had “the financial resources and personal fortitude to endure four different court proceedings” would be able to exercise their claimed constitutional right, while those plaintiffs “who will not or cannot afford this extensive litigation would be denied their right”). Indeed, forcing Plaintiffs to challengeeach of the “innumerable” statutes in piecemeal fashion is not only manifestly unfair to them, it is an enormous waste of resources, given that the underlying legal question is the same with respect to each statute at issue. Montana taxpayers, who will have to foot the State's legal bills for defending each of these “innumerable” lawsuits, should be appalled by the Court's and the Attorney General's approach here.

¶ 68 I think it is worth noting that the Court's and the Attorney General's approach is completely out of step with other courts around the country—federal and state. For example, Section 3 of the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), 1 U.S.C. § 7, defines “marriage” as a legal union between one man and one woman, and defines “spouse” as a person of the opposite sex who is a husband or a wife. Although these definitions have “varying impact on more than a thousand federal laws,” the Second Circuit Court of Appeals did not require the plaintiff to specifically identify those laws. Windsor v. United States, 699 F.3d 169, 180 (2d Cir.2012). To the contrary, the court proceeded to analyze her equal protection claim and concluded that “ homosexuals compose a class that is subject to heightened scrutiny,” that the class is “quasi-suspect” and thus subject to “intermediate scrutiny,” and that “DOMA's classification of same-sex spouses was not substantially related to an important government interest.” Windsor, 699 F.3d at 185, 188. Similarly, despite DOMA's “ramifying application throughout the U.S. Code” and its “effects on the numerous federal programs at issue,” the First Circuit Court of Appeals did not require the plaintiffs to identify the “economic and other benefits” impacted by DOMA. Massachusetts v. U.S. Dept. of Health and Human Servs., 682 F.3d 1, 5, 13 (1st Cir.2012). The court simply analyzed the constitutionality of excluding same-sex couples and concluded that “ Congress' denial of federal benefits to same-sex couples lawfully married in Massachusetts has not been adequately supported by any permissible federal interest.” Massachusetts, 682 F.3d at 16.

¶ 69 In New Jersey, different-sex married couples are entitled to “a vast array of economic and social benefits and privileges.” Lewis, 908 A.2d at 206. While same-sex couples enjoyed various rights under New Jersey's Domestic Partnership Act, they were still denied “many benefits and privileges” accorded to married couples. Lewis, 908 A.2d at 215. In other words, the Domestic Partnership Act “failed to bridge the inequality gap between committed same-sex couples and married opposite-sex couples.” Lewis, 908 A.2d at 215. The New Jersey Supreme Court noted a number of the rights afforded to married couples but denied to same-sex couples. The court did not require the plaintiffs, however, to go back to the trial court and re-file their constitutional challenge to this scheme—like this Court does in the present case—as “specific” challenges to “specific” statutes. Rather, the court quite sensibly and logically explained that the constitutional question is “whether there is a public need to deny committed same-sex partners the benefits and privileges available to heterosexual couples.” Lewis, 908 A.2d at 217. Ultimately, the court held that “denying to committed same-sex couples the financial and social benefits and privileges given to their married heterosexual counterparts bears no substantial relationship to a legitimate governmental purpose.” Lewis, 908 A.2d at 220.

¶ 70 The fact that there were “hundreds” of statutes relating to marriage and to marital benefits did not prevent the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts from ascertaining whether the exclusion of same-sex couples from those benefits violated the state constitution. Goodridge v. Dept. of Pub. Health, 440 Mass. 309, 798 N.E.2d 941, 955 (2003). The court noted some of the statutory benefits in its opinion, but saw no need “to be comprehensive.” Goodridge, 798 N.E.2d at 955. The Hawaii Supreme Court also saw no such need. In considering the same-sex couples' constitutional challenge, the court observed that “a multiplicity of rights and benefits” are contingent upon the status of marriage, but the court found it “unnecessary ... to engage in an encyclopedic recitation of all of them.” Baehr v. Lewin, 74 Haw. 530, 852 P.2d 44, 59 (1993).

¶ 71 The Vermont Supreme Court likewise had no difficulty analyzing the legality of excluding same-sex couples from the “broad array of legal benefits and protections incident to the marital relation, including access to a spouse's medical, life, and disability insurance, hospital visitation and other medical decisionmaking privileges, spousal support, intestate succession, homestead protections, and many other statutory protections.” Baker, 744 A.2d at 870. The court did not require the plaintiffs to specifically identify and specifically analyze the specific statutes. Rather, the court addressed the question common to each: “whether the exclusion of same-sex couples from the benefits and protections incident to marriage under Vermont law” is unconstitutional. Baker, 744 A.2d at 880. The court ultimately found “a constitutional obligation to extend to plaintiffs the common benefit, protection, and security that Vermont law provides opposite-sex married couples.” Baker, 744 A.2d at 886.

¶ 72 I could continue, but I think the point is clear. In refusing to issue a declaratory ruling as to Plaintiffs' constitutional rights, and in forcing them to instead litigate each statutory protection individually, this Court sets itself up as the only court in the country to follow such an approach. In so doing, the Court commits grievous error.

¶ 73 The instant case is no different than the cases cited above. “Marriage” in Montana is presently defined as “a personal relationship between a man and a woman arising out of a civil contract.” Section 40–1–103, MCA. Marriage between two persons of the same sex is prohibited. Section 40–1–401(1)(d), MCA; Mont. Const. art. XIII, § 7. Hence, by definition, a person cannot be the “spouse” of someone who is the same sex. Black's Law Dictionary 1533 (Bryan A. Garner ed., 9th ed., Thomson Reuters 2009) ( spouse: “a married person”). The State grants a broad array of legal benefits and protections to “spouses.” As but one example, § 37–19–904(2) (c), MCA, grants the surviving “spouse” the right to control the disposition of the remains of a deceased person. Same-sex couples are excluded from the operation of these statutes because, by definition, they cannot be “spouses” and because they are not encompassed within the scope of the statutes in some other way. See e.g. § 45–5–206, MCA (for purposes of partner or family member assault, “partners” means “spouses, former spouses, persons who have a child in common, and persons who have been or are currently in a dating or ongoing intimate relationship with a person of the opposite sex” (emphasis added)). Plaintiffs' claim here is the same as the challengers' claims in the above cases: excluding same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections of these laws is unconstitutional.

¶ 74 As detailed in the Declaratory Judgment section below, there is simply no basis in law or in reason for requiring Plaintiffs to present their constitutional claim within the context of a challenge to a specific spousal benefit, or for requiring them to pursue independent challenges to each benefit, or for requiring them to identify all of the discriminatory laws. The notion that they must “specifically identify” and “specifically analyze” each of the “innumerable” statutes is, in reality, nothing more than a straw-man argument that the Attorney General has invented, and this Court has adopted, to avoid a socially divisive issue. I cannot believe that if the statutes discriminated on the basis of race, national origin, or religious affiliation, rather than sexual orientation, the Court would concoct such an implausible procedural technicality as the Court does here to evade a legitimately presented constitutional question and deny the plaintiffs relief.

¶ 75 For all of these reasons, the Court's contention that it cannot issue a ruling on Plaintiffs' constitutional rights is devoid of any genuine or well-grounded underpinning. And so is the Court's suggestion that Plaintiffs still need “to develop an argument as to ... the level of constitutional scrutiny that should be applied to [the discriminatory] laws by the courts.” Opinion, ¶ 13. Plaintiffs devote entire sections of their briefs to this exact question, arguing that sexual orientation is a suspect class and that the denial of statutory benefits and obligations based on sexual orientation should be subject to heightened scrutiny. It is not clear whether the Court has overlooked these sections of Plaintiffs' briefs, or simply chosen to ignore them, but the argument is there. Perhaps the Court's view is that the level of scrutiny varies from statute to statute depending on “the nature of the State's interest.” Opinion, ¶ 13. That, however, would be quite the novel approach to constitutional law. Indeed, I am aware of no precedent, from any court in this country, holding that the level of scrutiny—rational basis, middle tier, or strict—is determined not by the classification or the constitutional right at issue, but by “the nature of the State's interest” in discriminating against the class or infringing the right. Such an approach turns equal protection and due process analysis on its head.

¶ 76 If the reader is baffled by what the Court is requiring of Plaintiffs, he or she is not alone. As a purely factual matter, there is no dispute that the State, by statute, makes certain benefits and obligations available to different-sex couples but denies same-sex couples access to those same benefits and obligations. The legal question common to every challenge Plaintiffs might lodge against these statutes is whether, under our Constitution, the State may categorically exclude homosexuals and bisexuals in committed intimate same-sex relationships from the opportunity to obtain the same statutory protections made available to heterosexuals and bisexuals in committed intimate different-sex relationships. There is no persuasive, let alone legitimate, reason why we cannot issue a ruling on this question. Even assuming, for the sake of argument, that “the nature of the State's interest” in excluding same-sex couples varies from statute to statute, this does not preclude us from declaring what Plaintiffs' rights are under traditional constitutional principles. We can rule—and I would rule—that sexual orientation is a suspect class and, therefore, that the State's interest in denying same-sex couples the opportunity to obtain the statutory protections offered to different-sex couples must be “compelling.” Such a ruling is permitted by the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act, and it would adequately resolve this dispute. At that point, the legislative and executive branches could take whatever steps are necessary to honor Plaintiffs' civil rights—as legislative and executive officers are constitutionally sworn to do (Mont. Const. art. III, § 3)—in accordance with our decision.

¶ 77 The Court tells Plaintiffs that they may amend their complaint and pursue further proceedings in the District Court. Opinion, ¶ 13. While this at least has the virtue of rescuing their claims from the District Court's outright dismissal, I cannot agree that this remedy is adequate. To the contrary, refusing to declare Plaintiffs' constitutional rights forthwith, and sending them back to the District Court for unnecessary re-litigation of a constitutional question they have squarely presented to us in the instant appeal, is itself an infringement of those rights. It must not be forgotten that “[t]he rights here asserted are, like all such rights, present rights; they are not merely hopes to some future enjoyment of some formalistic constitutional promise. The basic guarantees of our Constitution are warrants for the here and now and, unless there is an overwhelmingly compelling reason, they are to be promptly fulfilled.” Watson v. City of Memphis, 373 U.S. 526, 533, 83 S.Ct. 1314, 1318, 10 L.Ed.2d 529 (1963) (rejecting the City's request for further delay in meeting its constitutional obligation under the Fourteenth Amendment to desegregate its public parks and other municipal recreational facilities). Likewise, under Montana law, the courts of this State (including the Montana Supreme Court) are courts of justice. Section 3–1–101, MCA. “Courts of justice shall be open to every person, and speedy remedy afforded for every injury of person[.] ... Right and justice shall be administered without sale, denial, or delay.” Mont. Const. art. II, § 16. This fundamental constitutional right is not simply access to courts. It is access to justice—defined in Montana's organic law to mean a speedy remedy, to every person, for every injury of person, without delay.

¶ 78 Thus, as a matter of federal constitutional law and Montana constitutional law, Plaintiffs are entitled to a prompt determination of their constitutional rights vis-à-vis the State of Montana's admitted practice of making benefits and protections available to different-sex couples while categorically denying them to same-sex couples. Plaintiffs are also entitled to prompt rectification for any violations of these rights. Watson, 373 U.S. at 533, 83 S.Ct. at 1318 (“any deprivation of constitutional rights calls for prompt rectification”); Mont. Const. art. II, § 16 (“speedy remedy” shall be afforded for every injury). “It is axiomatic that ‘justice delayed is justice denied.’ ” State ex rel. Carlin v. Fifth Jud. Dist. Ct., 118 Mont. 127, 135, 164 P.2d 155, 159 (1945); cf. Christianson v. Colt Indus. Operating Corp., 486 U.S. 800, 816, 108 S.Ct. 2166, 2178, 100 L.Ed.2d 811 (1988) (“Perpetual litigation of any issue ... delays, and therefore threatens to deny, justice.”); Kloss v. Edward D. Jones & Co., 2002 MT 129, ¶ 58, 310 Mont. 123, 54 P.3d 1 (Nelson, Trieweiler, Leaphart, & Cotter, JJ., specially concurring) (“Constitutional rights that cannot be enforced are illusory. It is as if those rights cease to exist as legal rights.”). Evading and delaying a decision on the merits of Plaintiffs' constitutional claims, and requiring them to file seriatim challenges to “innumerable” statutes—each with the same, common legal issue—denies Plaintiffs access to justice just as clearly and as surely as if we had simply padlocked the courthouse doors. No class of litigants should be burdened with the emotional, financial, and time-related costs of this approach. No class of litigants should be treated in this draconian fashion. Our decision today makes a mockery of this Court's supposed commitment to access-to-justice principles. See In re the Estab. of an Access to Just. Commn., No. AF 11–0765 (Mont. May 22, 2012).

¶ 79 In light of the foregoing, I believe that rather than affirmatively protect Plaintiffs' civil rights as they are sworn to do, the Attorney General, the Legislature, and now, sadly, a majority of this Court have instead denied these persons justice and wrongly prolonged the State's discriminatory practices. In requiring Plaintiffs to jump through procedural hoops that we have never imposed on any other minority group, and in thus delaying the vindication of their constitutional rights, the Court conveys that gay, lesbian, and bisexual Montanans cannot expect to receive fairness, justice, respect, and equal treatment from Montana's courts. As I said at the outset, this is a black day for civil rights in Montana.

¶ 80 I now turn to a detailed discussion of the law supporting my conclusion that declaratory relief is appropriate here.

III. DECLARATORY JUDGMENT

¶ 81 Procedure should be the “handmaid of justice,” a means to an end. Instead ... procedure tends to become rigid, stereotyped, and over-technical, an end in itself, often seemingly oblivious to the practical needs of those to whose ills it is designed to minister. Litigants thus often become pawns in a game, the social cost of which is excessive and the result of which is frequently unnecessarily cumbersome and socially undesirable. Substantive rights often become the incidents of procedural fencing.


Allstate Ins. Co. v. Hayes, 442 Mich. 56, 499 N.W.2d 743, 746 (1993) (ellipsis in original) (quoting Edwin Borchard, Declaratory Judgments xiii (2d ed. 1941)).

A. Legal Principles

¶ 82 The National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws approved the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act in 1922. The Act has been adopted, substantially as drafted, in most states including Montana. See Unif. Declaratory Judms. Act, tbl. of jxns. and historical notes, 12 U.L.A. 331 (2008 & Supp.2012); Mont. Code Ann., Annotations 2012, at 1030; Title 27, chapter 8, MCA. The Act states that it is to be “so interpreted and construed as to effectuate its general purpose to make uniform the law of those states which enact it and to harmonize, as far as possible, with federal laws and regulations on the subject of declaratory judgments and decrees.” Section 27–8–103, MCA. Thus, it is appropriate to consider decisions from other jurisdictions when applying the Act. See e.g. Beahringer v. Page, 204 Ill.2d 363, 273 Ill.Dec. 784, 789 N.E.2d 1216, 1223 (2003) (“In interpreting the Illinois declaratory judgment statute, Illinois courts may look to the decisions of other states in interpreting the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act.”).

¶ 83 The purpose of the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act “is to settle and to afford relief from uncertainty and insecurity with respect to rights, status, and other legal relations.” Section 27–8–102, MCA. The Act relieves litigants of the common-law rule that no declaration of rights may be judicially adjudged unless a right has been violated. Boyds Civic Assn. v. Montgomery Co. Council, 309 Md. 683, 526 A.2d 598, 602 (1987). In other words, the Act renders disputes concerning legal rights and duties justiciable without proof of a wrong committed by one party against another. Hirschfield v. Bd. of Co. Commrs., 944 P.2d 1139, 1142 (Wyo.1997); see also Beahringer, 273 Ill.Dec. 784, 789 N.E.2d at 1223 (“The declaratory judgment procedure allows the court to take hold of a controversy one step sooner than normally—that is, after the dispute has arisen, but before steps are taken which give rise to claims for damages or other relief. The parties to the dispute can then learn the consequences of their action before acting.” (internal quotation marks omitted)).

¶ 84 Thus, we have recognized that declaratory relief serves “to liquidate uncertainties and controversies which might result in future litigation.” In re Dewar, 169 Mont. 437, 444, 548 P.2d 149, 154 (1976); accord Forty–Second Legis. Assembly v. Lennon, 156 Mont. 416, 421, 481 P.2d 330, 332 (1971) (“to eliminate or reduce a multiplicity of future litigation”); Beahringer, 273 Ill.Dec. 784, 789 N.E.2d at 1223 (“ ‘to afford security and relief against uncertainty so as to avoid potential litigation’ ”). Through declaratory relief, “ ‘parties between whom an actual controversy exists or between whom litigation is inevitable are enabled to have the issues speedily determined where their determination would be delayed to the possible injury of the one or the other if they were compelled to await the course of ordinary judicial proceedings.’ ” Automation Sys., Inc. v. Intel Corp., 501 F.Supp. 345, 347 (S.D.Iowa 1980) (quoting Anthony William Deller, Walker on Patents vol. 8, § 617, 65 (2d ed. 1973)). In this respect, “declaratory procedure operates prospectively, and not merely for the redress of past wrongs. It serves to set controversies at rest before they lead to repudiation of obligations, invasion of rights or commission of wrongs; in short, the remedy is to be used in the interests of preventive justice, to declare rights rather than execute them.” Babb v. Super. Ct., 3 Cal.3d 841, 92 Cal.Rptr. 179, 479 P.2d 379, 383 (1971) (alteration and internal quotation marks omitted).

¶ 85 To that end, the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act confers on courts the “power to declare rights, status, and other legal relations whether or not further relief is or could be claimed.Section 27–8–201, MCA (emphasis added). The declaration “may be either affirmative or negative in form and effect,” and it has “the force and effect of a final judgment or decree.” Section 27–8–201, MCA. The Act specifically provides that

[a]ny person interested under a deed, will, written contract, or other writings constituting a contract or whose rights, status, or other legal relations are affected by a statute, municipal ordinance, contract, or franchise may have determined any question of construction or validity arising under the instrument, statute, ordinance, contract, or franchise and obtain a declaration of rights, status, or other legal relations thereunder.
Section 27–8–202, MCA. The Act further provides, however, that this enumeration “does not limit or restrict the exercise of the general powers conferred in 27–8–201 in any proceeding where declaratory relief is sought in which a judgment or decree will terminate the controversy or remove an uncertainty.” Section 27–8–205, MCA. The Act “is to be liberally construed and administered,” § 27–8–102, MCA, and “[n]o action or proceeding shall be open to objection on the ground that a declaratory judgment or decree is prayed for,” § 27–8–201, MCA.

¶ 86 Lastly, it is well settled that declaratory procedure is appropriate to determine a constitutional question or to test a constitutional right. See e.g. MEA–MFT v. McCulloch, 2012 MT 211, 366 Mont. 266, 291 P.3d 1075;Snetsinger v. Mont. Univ. Sys., 2004 MT 390, 325 Mont. 148, 104 P.3d 445;McGillivray v. State, 1999 MT 3, 293 Mont. 19, 972 P.2d 804;McDonald v. State, 220 Mont. 519, 722 P.2d 598 (1986); Bd. of Regents v. Judge, 168 Mont. 433, 543 P.2d 1323 (1975). As the Washington Supreme Court has stated, “[d]eclaratory procedure is peculiarly well suited to the judicial determination of controversies concerning constitutional rights and ... the constitutionality of legislative action or inaction.” Seattle Sch. Dist. v. State, 90 Wash.2d 476, 585 P.2d 71, 80 (1978).

B. The District Court's Decision

¶ 87 Given these principles, the District Court clearly had power “to declare [Plaintiffs' constitutional] rights, status, and other legal relations”— whether or not further relief was or could be claimed—in order to “terminate the controversy” or “remove an uncertainty.” Sections 27–8–201, –205, MCA. The District Court did not deny that it has this power; in fact, Plaintiffs reminded the District Court that it has this power in their motion to alter or amend the judgment. The District Court, rather, simply failed to exercise it.

¶ 88 At this juncture it is necessary to describe Plaintiffs' Prayer for Relief, which is attached as Appendix 2 to this Dissent. It consists of nine numbered paragraphs. The first five paragraphs seek declaratory relief—specifically, a “declaration” that the State's categorical exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations which the State makes available to different-sex couples violates five separate rights in the Montana Constitution. The next two paragraphs seek injunctive relief: that the State be enjoined “from continuing to deny Plaintiffs and their families access to a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who marry,” and that the State be required “to offer same-sex couples and their families a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations that the State provides to different-sex couples who marry, but not the status or designation of marriage.” The final two paragraphs seek costs, attorney's fees, and such other relief as the court deems just and proper.

¶ 89 Curiously, while five of the nine paragraphs in the Prayer for Relief seek declaratory relief, the District Court focused exclusively on the question of injunctive relief. The court stated that “[t]he relief sought by Plaintiffs is contained in paragraph 7 of their prayer for relief.” Paragraph 7 requests an order requiring the State to offer same-sex couples and their families “a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations that the State provides to different-sex couples who marry, but not the status or designation of marriage.” The District Court interpreted this to mean that “Plaintiffs seek an order of this Court requiring the legislature to adopt a civil union or domestic partnership statutory scheme.”

¶ 90 The District Court questioned whether the issuance of such an order would be an appropriate exercise of the court's power. The District Court acknowledged that it has previously been willing to exercise its judicial power when it found “a specific statute applying to gay people” unconstitutional. See Gryczan v. State, No. BDV–93–1869 (Mont. 1st Jud. Dist. Feb. 16, 1996), aff'd, 283 Mont. 433, 942 P.2d 112 (1997). However, the District Court distinguished the present case from Gryczan on the ground that “what Plaintiffs want here is not a declaration of the unconstitutionality of a specific statute or set of statutes, but rather a direction to the legislature to enact a statutory arrangement.” The District Court opined that directing the Legislature to take such action “would launch this Court into a roiling maelstrom of policy issues without a constitutional compass.” The District Court also felt that it could not issue such an order without knowing “ all of the statutes that would be affected” (emphasis added).

¶ 91 The District Court further acknowledged that it has previously declared a statutory scheme unconstitutional and allowed the Legislature broad discretion to correct the unconstitutional portions of the statutes. See Columbia Falls Elem. Sch. Dist. v. State, No. BDV–02–0528, 2004 WL 844055 (Mont. 1st Jud. Dist. Apr. 15, 2004), aff'd, 2005 MT 69, 326 Mont. 304, 109 P.3d 257. But the District Court viewed Columbia Falls as distinguishable from the present case in that the court was dealing with “a discreet school funding formula” and “knew exactly what statutes would be affected” in the Columbia Falls case, whereas the present case involves “a not yet entirely specified array of statutes that deal with many different topics and were enacted over a variety of years.”

¶ 92 The District Court thus reached “the jurisprudential decision that Plaintiffs' requested relief constitutes an impermissible sojourn into the powers of the legislative branch.” Citing “the constitutional separation of powers” (Mont. Const. art. III, § 1), the District Court granted the Attorney General's motion to dismiss. The District Court posited that the proper way to address Plaintiffs' concerns would be through “specific suits directed at specific, identifiable statutes.”

¶ 93 With regard to the issue of injunctive relief, I do not fault Plaintiffs for including requests for such relief in their complaint. It was their prerogative to do so. See Title 27, chapter 19, MCA. Likewise, however, I do not fault the District Court for declining to order injunctive relief at this stage. The District Court noted several factors which, in the court's view, weighed against the issuance of a judicial order requiring the Legislature to enact the “statutory structure” requested by Plaintiffs. I cannot conclude that the District Court abused its discretion in this regard. See Krutzfeldt Ranch, LLC v. Pinnacle Bank, 2012 MT 15, ¶ 13, 363 Mont. 366, 272 P.3d 635 (“the denial of a temporary or permanent injunction is reviewed for ‘manifest abuse of discretion’ ”).

¶ 94 That being said, none of the factors identified by the District Court regarding Plaintiffs' request for injunctive relief excuse or justify that court's complete and utter failure to grant Plaintiffs' request for declaratory relief. It bears repeating that the District Court had “power to declare rights, status, and other legal relations whether or not further relief is or could be claimed.Section 27–8–201, MCA (emphasis added). Indeed, “ ‘[a] declaratory judgment or decree is one which simply declares the rights of the parties or expresses the opinion of the court on a question of law, without ordering anything to be done; its distinctive characteristic being that the declaration stands by itself, and no executory process follows as of course....’ ” Black v. Siler, 96 Ariz. 102, 392 P.2d 572, 574 (1964) (emphasis added) (quoting Clein v. Kaplan, 201 Ga. 396, 40 S.E.2d 133, 137 (1946)). The District Court had the power to issue a declaration if for no other reason than to “remove an uncertainty” regarding Plaintiffs' rights. Section 27–8–205, MCA. Again, the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act “is to be liberally construed and administered,” § 27–8–102, MCA, and “[n]o action or proceeding shall be open to objection on the ground that a declaratory judgment or decree is prayed for,” § 27–8–201, MCA. Thus, the fact that the District Court felt precluded from granting Plaintiffs' requests for injunctive relief was not a valid legal basis for ignoring their requests for declaratory relief. These are distinct forms of relief, and a court's ability to grant the latter does not depend in any way whatsoever on its ability to grant the former. Section 27–8–201, MCA.

¶ 95 There is likewise no merit to the proposition that declaratory relief cannot be granted without first identifying “all” of the statutes that would be affected by the ruling. First of all, as a factual matter, Plaintiffs provided the District Court with a list, appearing to be exhaustive, of the Montana statutes that confer benefits and protections on married couples—benefits and protections that are unavailable to Plaintiffs because they cannot marry. See Appendix 1 to this Dissent. The District Court thus had what it claimed it needed: a list of “all of the statutes that would be affected” by the court's ruling. Yet, rather than address Plaintiffs' requests for declaratory relief in light of this list—which Plaintiffs had provided at the District Court's behest—the District Court inexplicably took no action at all and thus caused their motion to alter or amend the judgment to be denied by operation of law. SeeM.R. Civ. P. 59(g) (2009).

¶ 96 Secondly, this same proposition—that declaratory relief cannot be granted without first identifying “all” of the statutes that would be affected by the ruling—was asserted, and rejected, in Spates v. Montgomery Co., 87 Md.App. 590, 590 A.2d 1074, 1076 (1991). There, the government argued that “by failing to identify particular statutes he regards as unconstitutional, Spates has not presented a justiciable issue.” Spates, 590 A.2d at 1077. The Maryland Court of Special Appeals agreed that Spates' complaint was “poorly drawn and seriously lacking in specifics.” Spates, 590 A.2d at 1077. Yet, the court observed that Spates' “basic point” was that the government's failure to tax personal property placed an unfair, disproportionate, and non-uniform tax burden on the owners of real property. Spates, 590 A.2d at 1077. From this, the court reasoned that

the failure to identify particular sections of the Tax–Property article of the Code is really not telling in this case. Spates has challenged the system of taxation authorized by law, which includes those sections defining terms, imposing the property tax, determining the kinds of property to be taxed, establishing the method of assessment, and providing for the collection of the tax. Given the nature of his attack, it would, as he contends, be well-nigh impossible, and quite unnecessary in our view, to pick through the entire Tax Code and identify only those specific statutes or parts of statutes that directly support the system he challenges.
Spates, 590 A.2d at 1077.

¶ 97 Plaintiffs' challenge in the present case is not directed at Montana's system of taxation; it is directed at Montana's system of statutory benefits and protections accorded to married couples. Nevertheless, Spates' reasoning is pertinent here. Indeed, the fact that the Legislature has spread the benefits and protections throughout the Code, rather than collecting them all in a single title and chapter, cannot immunize the system from challenge and review.

¶ 98 The one feature common to each of the benefits and protections is that they are granted to “spouses,” or on the basis of “marriage” to a “husband” or “wife.” Under current Montana law, only heterosexuals and bisexuals in different-sex relationships can get “married” and thus become “spouses,” “husbands,” and “wives”; homosexuals and bisexuals in same-sex relationships are not allowed to marry. Mont. Const. art. XIII, § 7; §§ 40–1–103, –401(1)(d), MCA; Black's Law Dictionary 810, 1533, 1735 ( spouse: “a married person”; husband: “[a] married man”; wife: “[a] married woman”). As a result, same-sex couples are not encompassed within these benefits and protections. Plaintiffs challenge this scheme as unconstitutional—i.e., the fact that the State systematically denies them “the opportunity” to obtain the benefits and protections made available to different-sex couples. Again, Plaintiffs do not ask to be married; they would be satisfied if “the opportunity” to obtain the benefits and protections were provided through some sort of alternative method distinct from “marriage.” Whether this claim implicates one statute or a hundred, it is quite unnecessary for Plaintiffs to identify them all in this lawsuit in order to obtain a declaratory ruling. Paragraphs 1 through 5 of the Prayer for Relief seek only a “declaration” that this disparate treatment— the existence of which no one disputes—violates the Montana Constitution. The District Court and this Court, in turn, may decree that it is unconstitutional to deny same-sex couples the opportunity to obtain the civil protections made available to different-sex couples, absent a compelling state interest. Once that is done, the Legislature can identify the problem statutes and amend them. Indeed, the Legislature did just that in 2009 when it passed House Bill 37, titled “An Act Gender Neutralizing and Conforming Titles 10 through 90 of the Montana Code Annotated to Current Bill Drafting Standards....” This single piece of legislation, the text of which spans 967 pages of the 2009 Session Laws, simultaneously amended 2,876 statutes. Surely if the Legislature can identify several thousand statutes needing to be “gender neutralized,” the Legislature can identify a few hundred statutes needing to be “sexual-orientation neutralized.”

¶ 99 We have said that “[t]he decision to dismiss a complaint for declaratory relief is within the sound discretion of the district court.” Renville v. Farmers Ins. Exch., 2003 MT 103, ¶ 9, 315 Mont. 295, 69 P.3d 217. We have also held, however, that the “[f]ailure of a district court to exercise discretion is itself an abuse of discretion.” Clark Fork Coalition v. Mont. Dept. of Envtl. Quality, 2008 MT 407, ¶ 43, 347 Mont. 197, 197 P.3d 482; cf. Spates, 590 A.2d at 1076 (“Having failed to find a legitimate reason not to declare the rights of the parties, it was incumbent upon the court to do so.”). That is what happened here when the District Court dismissed Plaintiffs' complaint based on their requested injunctive relief, without addressing their requested declaratory relief. In so doing, the District Court wrongly conflated these two forms of relief. The District Court failed to recognize that one of the purposes of the Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act is “[t]o enable public duties and powers to be established without the cumbersome and technical prerequisites of mandamus, certiorari, injunction, prohibition, or habeas corpus.” Edwin Borchard, Declaratory Judgments 288 (2d ed. 1941). The District Court overlooked the fact that while a motion to dismiss may be used in a declaratory judgment proceeding “to challenge the legal availability or appropriateness of the remedy,” a motion to dismiss should “ seldom, if ever, ... be sustained or the complaint dismissed without a declaration one way or the other of the rights of the parties.” Spates, 590 A.2d at 1076 (emphases added, brackets and internal quotation marks omitted); cf. Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 468–69, 94 S.Ct. 1209, 1220, 39 L.Ed.2d 505 (1974) (a federal court has “the duty to decide the appropriateness and the merits of the declaratory request irrespective of its conclusion as to the propriety of the issuance of the injunction” (internal quotation marks omitted)); James Wm. Moore, Moore's Federal Practice vol. 2, § 12.34[1][b], 12–81 (3d ed., Matthew Bender 2012) (“Consistently with their obligation to construe plaintiffs' allegations liberally, courts will not dismiss for failure to state a claim merely because the complaint requests inappropriate relief.”).

¶ 100 I am thus in complete agreement with Plaintiffs' statement, in their motion to alter or amend the judgment, that “dismissal of the entire action based solely on one request for injunctive relief reflects a manifest error of law as there are five other requests for declaratory judgment upon which this Court may properly rule.” The District Court erred, as a matter of law, in its treatment of Plaintiffs' request for declaratory relief, and the District Court's judgment must therefore be reversed to that extent.

C. This Court's “Justiciability” Rationale

¶ 101 Like the District Court, this Court also lumps Plaintiffs' requests for injunctive relief and declaratory relief into a single analysis. Opinion, ¶ 9. Doing so is error for the reasons just discussed. The Court does appear, however, to reject Plaintiffs' claims using a somewhat different rationale. Specifically, the Court asserts that this case is not “justiciable” because a ruling in Plaintiffs' favor “would not terminate the uncertainty or controversy giving rise to this proceeding” and because Plaintiffs are asking this Court to “determine speculative matters,” “declare social status,” “give advisory opinions,” or “give abstract opinions.” Opinion, ¶ 9. In all respects, the Court is mistaken.

¶ 102 First of all, a declaratory judgment is itself “remedial.” Section 27–8–102, MCA. A declaratory judgment or decree is one which simply declares the rights of the parties or expresses the opinion of the court on a question of law, without ordering anything to be done; the declaration stands by itself, and no executory process follows as of course. Black, 392 P.2d at 574;Clein, 40 S.E.2d at 137;§ 27–8–201, MCA. The Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act permits courts “to settle and to afford relief from uncertainty and insecurity.” Section 27–8–102, MCA. A declaratory judgment is appropriate if for no other reason than to “remove an uncertainty.” Section 27–8–205, MCA.

¶ 103 The Court's contention that a declaratory judgment would not terminate the uncertainty or controversy giving rise to this proceeding is simply untrue. There is no dispute that the State offers a variety of benefits and protections to committed intimate couples, but only different-sex couples have the opportunity to obtain them. This regime gives preferential treatment to heterosexuals and bisexuals committed to a person of the opposite sex, and disfavors homosexuals and bisexuals committed to a person of the same sex. Plaintiffs' requests for declaratory relief raise one legal question: Is it constitutionally permissible for the State to deny same-sex couples the opportunity to obtain the benefits and protections made available to different-sex couples? In other words, is it constitutionally permissible for Montana's government to treat Plaintiffs differently based on their sexual orientation? That is the “uncertainty or controversy” in this case. We may resolve it—and, for the reasons detailed in the Constitutional Analysis section below, I would resolve it—by holding that sexual orientation is a suspect class and that any disparate treatment between committed intimate same-sex couples and different-sex married couples is subject to “strict scrutiny” review. Such a ruling would answer and resolve Plaintiffs' requests for declaratory relief.

¶ 104 Secondly, there is no merit to the Court's suggestion that Plaintiffs have asked us to determine speculative matters, declare social status, or give an abstract opinion. This dismissive portrayal of Plaintiffs' complaint is insulting and disrespectful. There is nothing “speculative” about the discrimination Plaintiffs have experienced—some of it private, some of it state-imposed—as described in their affidavits. The State itself does not deny that Plaintiffs have suffered economic and emotional harm due to their sexual orientation and that Plaintiffs' relationships are treated differently than their different-sex counterparts under the law. Plaintiffs do not ask or need this Court to declare their “social status.” Plaintiffs are acutely aware of their social status. They ask this Court, rather, to declare and uphold their constitutional rights. There is nothing “speculative” or “abstract” about this claim.

¶ 105 Lastly, we have previously defined nonjusticiable advisory opinions as “opinions issued by the court in response to a request from some other branch of government, such as the legislative or executive, asking for information concerning matters of law.” In re Secret Grand Jury Inquiry, 170 Mont. 354, 357, 553 P.2d 987, 990 (1976). That clearly is not the case here. More recently, we have stated that an advisory opinion is “one advising what the law would be upon a hypothetical state of facts or upon an abstract proposition.” Plan Helena, Inc. v. Helena Regl. Airport Auth. Bd., 2010 MT 26, ¶ 12, 355 Mont. 142, 226 P.3d 567. That too is not the case here. The underlying state of facts is not “hypothetical,” nor is the proposition “ abstract.” Plaintiffs are being denied access to statutory benefits and protections which the State, in its discretion, has chosen to make available to different-sex couples.

¶ 106 In Secret Grand Jury Inquiry, this Court articulated what constitutes a “justiciable controversy” for purposes of obtaining a declaratory judgment:

First, a justiciable controversy requires that parties have existing and genuine, as distinguished from theoretical, rights or interests. Second, the controversy must be one upon which the judgment of the court may effectively operate, as distinguished from a debate or argument invoking a purely political, administrative, philosophical or academic conclusion. Third, it must be a controversy the judicial determination of which will have the effect of a final judgment in law or decree in equity upon the rights, status or legal relationships of one or more of the real parties in interest, or lacking these qualities be of such an overriding public moment as to constitute the legal equivalent of all of them.
170 Mont. at 357, 553 P.2d at 990.

¶ 107 We have repeated this test in numerous cases,

and recently applied the test in Chipman v. N.W. Healthcare Corp., 2012 MT 242, ¶¶ 19–23, 366 Mont. 450, 288 P.3d 193. Here, the rights Plaintiffs invoke (ArticleII, Sections 3, 4, 10, and 17 of the Montana Constitution) are obviously not theoretical. They are “existing and genuine” constitutional rights. Second, a judgment on whether the State may make statutory benefits and protections available to different-sex couples, but categorically deny them to same-sex couples, “will effectively operate to settle the issues at hand.” Chipman, ¶ 22. I am not persuaded that it is necessary to litigate “the nature of the State's interest” with respect to each individual statute. Opinion, ¶ 13. But even assuming, for the sake of argument, that the nature of the State's interest in excluding same-sex couples varies from statute to statute, the present action can definitively settle the nature of Plaintiffs' constitutional rights—rights that are the same regardless of the statute at issue. There is no indication, therefore, that a declaration here would be “purely political, administrative, philosophical or academic.” Chipman, ¶ 22. Finally, in considering “the main thrust” of this lawsuit, Chipman, ¶ 23, this Court has been asked to determine the constitutional relationship of the parties. In particular, we must determine whether the Constitution requires that when the State offers legal benefits and protections to persons in committed intimate relationships, it must do so evenhandedly, without discriminating on the basis of sexual orientation. This controversy directly involves the rights, status, and legal relationships of the parties. Chipman, ¶ 23;see also Plan Helena, ¶ 9 (the controversy must be “definite and concrete, touching legal relations of parties having adverse legal interests” (internal quotation marks omitted)). Accordingly, it is a justiciable controversy under the foregoing three-part test.

See Lee v. State, 195 Mont. 1, 6, 635 P.2d 1282, 1284–85 (1981); Brisendine v. Dept. of Commerce, 253 Mont. 361, 364, 833 P.2d 1019, 1021 (1992); Gryczan v. State, 283 Mont. 433, 442, 942 P.2d 112, 117 (1997); Northfield Ins. Co. v. Mont. Assn. of Counties, 2000 MT 256, ¶ 12, 301 Mont. 472, 10 P.3d 813;Powder River County v. State, 2002 MT 259, ¶ 102, 312 Mont. 198, 60 P.3d 357;Montana–Dakota Utils. Co. v. City of Billings, 2003 MT 332, ¶ 9, 318 Mont. 407, 80 P.3d 1247;Advocs. for Educ., Inc. v. Mont. Dept. of Nat. Resources & Conserv., 2004 MT 230, ¶ 12, 322 Mont. 429, 97 P.3d 553;Skinner v. Allstate Ins. Co., 2005 MT 323, ¶ 15, 329 Mont. 511, 127 P.3d 359;Miller v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 2007 MT 85, ¶ 8, 337 Mont. 67, 155 P.3d 1278.

D. Summary

¶ 108 In sum, the Court errs in holding that this case is nonjusticiable. In adopting its statute-by-statute approach, the Court not only fails to follow Montana's own statutory commands, but also sets itself apart as the non-uniform black sheep in the otherwise Uniform Declaratory Judgments Act states.

¶ 109 Courts have “power to declare rights, status, and other legal relations whether or not further relief is or could be claimed.” Section 27–8–201, MCA. This power “is to be liberally construed and administered” to permit courts “to settle and to afford relief from uncertainty and insecurity.” Section 27–8–102, –205, MCA. Through a declaratory judgment proceeding, “a multiplicity of suits can be avoided, while an adequate, expedient, and inexpensive remedy can be afforded for litigants in a single action.” Thomas v. Cilbe, Inc., 104 So.2d 397, 403 (Fla.App.1958).

¶ 110 Here, the declaratory issue is whether the Montana Constitution prohibits the State from excluding same-sex partners from the opportunity to obtain the benefits and protections that the State makes available to different-sex partners. There is no need to identify “all” of the potentially offending statutes in order to issue a ruling on this legal question, nor is there a need to pursue each statutory challenge separately. It is sufficient to declare the constitutional standard applicable to Plaintiffs' claim—an issue which Plaintiffs have raised and briefed. And for the reasons discussed below, I would hold that sexual orientation is a suspect class under Article II, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution and that discrimination based on sexual orientation in the provision of statutory benefits and protections is subject to “strict scrutiny” review. I would reverse the District Court's judgment and direct it to enter such an order. I dissent from this Court's failure and refusal to do so.

¶ 111 As for the injunctions Plaintiffs request, I do not believe it is necessary to order such relief at this point. It is sufficient to declare Plaintiffs' constitutional rights so as to remove the apparent uncertainty concerning those rights. Sections 27–8–201, –205, MCA. Rather than proceed to direct the State how to remedy the problem, it is prudent to do what was done in the Columbia Falls and Snetsinger cases and permit the legislative and executive branches to address and resolve the matter in the first instance, in accordance with our constitutional interpretation, as those officers are sworn to do (Mont. Const. art. III, § 3). See Borchard, Declaratory Judgments 279–80 (“The declaratoryaction proceeds on the assumption that a mild remedy will often satisfy, that responsible defendants, like government officials or large corporations, do not need more than a declaration of the law to obey it and that a coercive procedure under such circumstances is an expensive and often unnecessary luxury.”). Indeed, this is exactly what happened following our decision in Snetsinger, where we concluded that the Montana University System's policy of treating unmarried same-sex couples differently than unmarried different-sex couples in the provision of health benefits violated the Montana Constitution. Within three months, the Board of Regents had approved—unanimously, no less—a new insurance policy that would allow University System employees to obtain health coverage for gay and lesbian partners. See Regents Approve Same–Sex Insurance Policy, Missoulian (Mar. 18, 2005).

¶ 112 Plaintiffs here contend that entering a declaratory judgment regarding their constitutional rights “would serve the courts' primary function of adjudicating citizens' rights under the Constitution, while allowing the coordinate branches of government a reasonable opportunity to bring the State's conduct into compliance with the Constitution.” I agree and, thus, would affirm the District Court's denial of injunctive relief, with the understanding that Plaintiffs may again pursue such relief if it becomes necessary in the future to do so. See e.g. Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 744 A.2d 864, 886, 887 (1999) (“We hold only that plaintiffs are entitled under Chapter I, Article 7, of the Vermont Constitution to obtain the same benefits and protections afforded by Vermont law to married opposite-sex couples. We do not purport to infringe upon the prerogatives of the Legislature to craft an appropriate means of addressing this constitutional mandate.... In the event that the benefits and protections in question are not statutorily granted, plaintiffs may petition this Court to order the remedy they originally sought.”).

¶ 113 Having detailed my reasons for disagreeing with the District Court's and this Court's procedural dispositions of the case, I now provide the legal analysis underlying my conclusions that sexual orientation is a suspect class and, thus, that treating same-sex couples differently than different-sex couples is subject to strict scrutiny review.

IV. CONSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS

¶ 114 [I]n view of the constitution, in the eye of the law, there is in this country no superior, dominant, ruling class of citizens. There is no caste here. Our Constitution ... neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens. In respect of civil rights, all citizens are equal before the law.


Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537, 559, 16 S.Ct. 1138, 1146, 41 L.Ed. 256 (1896) (Harlan, J., dissenting).

¶ 115 Plaintiffs contend that the State's exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the benefits and protections which the State makes available to different-sex couples violates five fundamental constitutional rights: to pursue safety, health, and happiness (Mont. Const. art. II, § 3), to equal protection of the laws (§ 4), to individual dignity (§ 4), to individual privacy (§ 10), and to due process of law (§ 17). Because I conclude that the Equal Protection Clause (which happens to be Plaintiffs' primary argument) is sufficient to resolve this case, I focus my analysis there and do not address Plaintiffs' arguments under Article II, Sections 3, 10, or 17. At the conclusion of my equal protection discussion, however, I briefly discuss Article II, Section 4's Dignity Clause and the additional support it provides for Plaintiffs' claim.

A. Religious, Moral, and Political Beliefs

¶ 116 At the outset, it is important to emphasize two preliminary points made by various courts which have addressed these issues.

¶ 117 First, although the question whether the State may exclude same-sex couples from the benefits and protections that it provides to different-sex married couples “arouses deeply-felt religious, moral, and political beliefs[,o]ur constitutional responsibility to consider the legal merits of issues properly before us provides no exception for the controversial case.” Baker v. State, 170 Vt. 194, 744 A.2d 864, 867 (1999). Courts have a duty to uphold the constitutional rights of all parties, regardless of how unpopular they or their cause may be. See e.g. Gryczan v. State, 283 Mont. 433, 942 P.2d 112 (1997) (upholding the constitutional right of homosexuals to engage in private, consensual, noncommercial sexual conduct with other adults free of governmental interference or regulation); Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 109 S.Ct. 2533, 105 L.Ed.2d 342 (1989) (upholding Johnson's First Amendment right to burn an American flag); Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 89 S.Ct. 1827, 23 L.Ed.2d 430 (1969) (upholding a Ku Klux Klan leader's First Amendment right to threaten “revengeance” if the “suppression” of the white race continues); Varnum v. Brien, 763 N.W.2d 862, 875 (Iowa 2009) (a statute inconsistent with the Constitution “must be declared void, even though it may be supported by strong and deep-seated traditional beliefs and popular opinion”); see also State v. Finley, 276 Mont. 126, 135, 915 P.2d 208, 214 (1996) (this Court has the “obligation” to protect individual rights); Washington v. Seattle Sch. Dist., 458 U.S. 457, 486, 102 S.Ct. 3187, 3203, 73 L.Ed.2d 896 (1982) (the Judiciary has a “special role in safeguarding the interests of those groups that are relegated to such a position of political powerlessness as to command extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process” (internal quotation marks omitted)); Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 635, 6 S.Ct. 524, 535, 29 L.Ed. 746 (1886) (“It is the duty of courts to be watchful for the constitutional rights of the citizen, and against any stealthy encroachments thereon.”).

¶ 118 Second, and along these same lines, the proper resolution of this case “does not turn on the religious or moral debate over intimate same-sex relationships, but rather on the statutory and constitutional basis for the exclusion of same-sex couples from the secular benefits and protections offered married couples.” Baker, 744 A.2d at 867. As aptly stated by the United States Supreme Court,

for centuries there have been powerful voices to condemn homosexual conduct as immoral. The condemnation has been shaped by religious beliefs, conceptions of right and acceptable behavior, and respect for the traditional family. For many persons these are not trivial concerns but profound and deep convictions accepted as ethical and moral principles to which they aspire and which thus determine the course of their lives. These considerations do not answer the question before us, however. The issue is whether the majority may use the power of the State to enforce these views on the whole society through operation of [its] law[s]. Our obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code.
Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 571, 123 S.Ct. 2472, 2480, 156 L.Ed.2d 508 (2003) (internal quotation marks omitted). Speaking to this same subject, this Court has likewise observed that

it is not the function of this or of any court to interpret the law on the basis of what may be morally acceptable or unacceptable to society at any given time.... Our Constitution does not protect morality; it does, however, guarantee to all persons, whether in the majority or in a minority, those certain basic freedoms and rights which are set forth in the Declaration of Rights.... Regardless that majoritarian morality may be expressed in the public-policy pronouncements of the legislature, it remains the obligation of the courts—and of this Court in particular—to scrupulously support, protect and defend those rights and liberties guaranteed to all persons under our Constitution.
Gryczan, 283 Mont. at 454–55, 942 P.2d at 125;see also Alaska Civ. Liberties Union v. State, 122 P.3d 781, 783 (Alaska 2005) (“Irrelevant to our analysis must be personal, moral, or religious beliefs—held deeply by many—about whether persons should enter into intimate same-sex relationships or whether same-sex domestic partners should be permitted to marry.”).

¶ 119 The upshot of these principles is that fundamental rights are not subject to filteringthrough the sieve of majoritarian morality or religious doctrine. Indeed, “the fact that the governing majority in a State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for upholding a law prohibiting the practice; neither history nor tradition could save a law prohibiting miscegenation from constitutional attack.” Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 577–78, 123 S.Ct. at 2483 (internal quotation marks omitted); see Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 87 S.Ct. 1817, 18 L.Ed.2d 1010 (1967) (invaliding antimiscegenation laws). The purpose of the federal Bill of Rights, like Montana's Declaration of Rights,

was to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of majorities and officials and to establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts. One's right to life, liberty, and property, to free speech, a free press, freedom of worship and assembly, and other fundamental rights [including equal protection of the laws] may not be submitted to vote; they depend on the outcome of no elections.
West Virginia State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 638, 63 S.Ct. 1178, 1185–86, 87 L.Ed. 1628 (1943). Our responsibility “is to protect constitutional rights of individuals ... even when the rights have not yet been broadly accepted, were at one time unimagined, or challenge a deeply ingrained practice or law viewed to be impervious to the passage of time.” Varnum, 763 N.W.2d at 875.

B. Equal Protection Principles

¶ 120 The United States Constitution and the Montana Constitution both command that no person shall be denied “the equal protection of the laws.” U.S. Const. amend. XIV; Mont. Const. art. II, § 4. Although the basic principles underlying these two provisions are the same, this Court has held that Article II, Section 4 provides greater individual protection than the Fourteenth Amendment. Snetsinger v. Mont. Univ. Sys., 2004 MT 390, ¶ 15, 325 Mont. 148, 104 P.3d 445.

¶ 121 “The guaranty of equal protection of the laws is a pledge of the protection of equal laws.” Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634, 116 S.Ct. 1620, 1628, 134 L.Ed.2d 855 (1996) (internal quotation marks omitted). It is “essentially a direction that all persons similarly situated should be treated alike.” City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 439, 105 S.Ct. 3249, 3254, 87 L.Ed.2d 313 (1985); accord Snetsinger, ¶ 15.

“[T]here is no more effective practical guaranty against arbitrary and unreasonable government than to require that the principles of law which officials would impose upon a minority must be imposed generally. Conversely, nothing opens the door to arbitrary action so effectively as to allow those officials to pick and choose only a few to whom they will apply legislation and thus to escape the political retribution that might be visited upon them if larger numbers were affected. Courts can take no better measure to assure that laws will be just than to require that laws be equal in operation.”
Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 454, 92 S.Ct. 1029, 1038–39, 31 L.Ed.2d 349 (1972) (quoting Ry. Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U.S. 106, 112–13, 69 S.Ct. 463, 466–67, 93 L.Ed. 533 (1949) (Jackson, J., concurring)). The Equal Protection guaranty “requires the democratic majority to accept for themselves and their loved ones what they impose on you and me.” Cruzan v. Dir., Missouri Dept. of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 300–01, 110 S.Ct. 2841, 2863, 111 L.Ed.2d 224 (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring).

¶ 122 Of course, the “promise that no person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws must coexist with the practical necessity that most legislation classifies for one purpose or another, with resulting disadvantage to various groups or persons.” Romer, 517 U.S. at 631, 116 S.Ct. at 1627. The general rule, therefore, is that if a law neither burdens a constitutional right nor targets a suspect or quasi-suspect class, then the courts will uphold the legislative classification so long as it bears a rational relationship to some legitimate governmental objective. However, if the classification disadvantages a suspect or quasi-suspect class or impinges upon the exercise of a constitutional right, then the classification is subject to heightened scrutiny. See Romer, 517 U.S. at 631, 116 S.Ct. at 1627; Cleburne, 473 U.S. at 440–41, 105 S.Ct. at 3254–55;Snetsinger, ¶¶ 17–19.

C. Framework

¶ 123 “Proper equal protection analysis involves identifying the classes involved, determining whether they are similarly situated and then using the appropriate level of scrutiny to determine if the statute is constitutional.” Bustell v. AIG Claims Serv., Inc., 2004 MT 362, ¶ 20, 324 Mont. 478, 105 P.3d 286;accord Reesor v. Montana State Fund, 2004 MT 370, ¶¶ 10, 13, 15, 325 Mont. 1, 103 P.3d 1019. While we have stated the “similarly situated” requirement in numerous cases, see e.g. Snetsinger, ¶ 16;State v. Egdorf, 2003 MT 264, ¶ 15, 317 Mont. 436, 77 P.3d 517;Powell v. State Compen. Ins. Fund, 2000 MT 321, ¶ 22, 302 Mont. 518, 15 P.3d 877, we have not fleshed out the meaning of this term. Federal caselaw provides some guidance on this point.

¶ 124 The federal framework for analyzing equal protection claims is the same as the Montana framework. The first step is to identify the State's classification of groups. Freeman v. City of Santa Ana, 68 F.3d 1180, 1187 (9th Cir.1995). To accomplish this, a plaintiff can show that the law is applied in a discriminatory manner or imposes different burdens on different classes of people. Freeman, 68 F.3d at 1187. Once the plaintiff establishes a governmental classification, it is necessary to identify a “similarly situated” class against which the plaintiff's class can be compared. Freeman, 68 F.3d at 1187. This is necessary because “[d]iscrimination cannot exist in a vacuum; it can be found only in the unequal treatment of people in similar circumstances.” Atty. Gen. of U.S. v. Irish People, Inc., 684 F.2d 928, 946 (D.C.Cir.1982). “The goal of identifying a similarly situated class ... is to isolate the factor allegedly subject to impermissible discrimination. The similarly situated group is the control group.” United States v. Aguilar, 883 F.2d 662, 706 (9th Cir.1989). Although the formula for determining whether two groups are “similarly situated” for equal protection purposes “is not always susceptible to precise demarcation,” Marrero–Gutierrez v. Molina, 491 F.3d 1, 9 (1st Cir.2007), the question is essentially whether the plaintiff's group is “roughly equivalent” to the control group, Tapalian v. Tusino, 377 F.3d 1, 6 (1st Cir.2004), in “all relevant respects” other than the factor constituting the alleged discrimination, Aguilar, 883 F.2d at 706;Nordlinger v. Hahn, 505 U.S. 1, 10, 112 S.Ct. 2326, 2331, 120 L.Ed.2d 1 (1992). “Exact correlation is neither likely nor necessary, but the cases must be fair congeners.” Tapalian, 377 F.3d at 6 (internal quotation marks omitted). Lastly, if it is demonstrated that a cognizable class is treated differently, the court analyzes whether the distinction made between the groups is justified under the appropriate level of scrutiny. United States v. Lopez–Flores, 63 F.3d 1468, 1472 (9th Cir.1995).

D. Classification and “Similarly Situated” Analysis

¶ 125 As discussed, the State grants various benefits and obligations to married persons, which is accomplished through the use of such terms as “husband,” “wife,” “spouse,” or “married” in the various statutes.

The State contends, therefore, that the statutes create “a marital classification.” In the State's view, “[t]he different classes involved here are married couples, who by definition are capable of receiving spousal benefits, and unmarried couples, who by definition are not capable of receiving spousal benefits.” The State further argues that married couples and unmarried couples are not similarly situated because married couples are formally recognized under the law and unmarried couples are not. Thus, the State concludes that Plaintiffs' equal protection claim must fail. One of the State's amici (Montana Family Foundation) similarly argues that Plaintiffs' claim fails because “all unmarried couples are treated alike under Montana law.”

See e.g. § 15–61–102(3), MCA (“ ‘Dependent’ means the spouse of the employee or account holder....”); § 19–6–505(2), MCA (“Upon the retired member's death, the retirement benefit must be paid to the member's surviving spouse, if there is one.”); § 27–1–515, MCA (“The rights of personal relations forbid ... the abduction or enticement of a wife from the wife's husband or a husband from the husband's wife....”); § 39–71–116(4), MCA (“ ‘Beneficiary’ means ... a surviving spouse living with or legally entitled to be supported by the deceased at the time of injury....”); § 40–2–102, MCA (“Insofar as each is able, the husband and wife shall support each other out of their property and labor.”); § 40–2–108, MCA (“A married person may be a personal representative, guardian, conservator, or trustee and may personally be bound and may bind the estate the person represents without any act or assent on the part of the person's spouse.”); § 50–9–106(2), MCA (“The authority to consent or to withhold consent under subsection (1) may be exercised by the following individuals, in order of priority: (a) the spouse of the individual....”); § 72–2–412, MCA (“A decedent's surviving spouse is entitled to a homestead allowance of $20,000.”).

¶ 126 These arguments are incorrect—both in identifying the pertinent classification and in applying the “similarly situated” concept. It is true that the statutes, on their face, classify based on marital status. But, as we have recognized, it is sometimes necessary to look beyond the face of a classification in order to ascertain the true distinction being drawn. In Bankers Life & Cas. Co. v. Peterson, 263 Mont. 156, 866 P.2d 241 (1993), for example, this Court did not treat “normal pregnancy and childbirth” as a classification between pregnant persons and non-pregnant persons—the approach the State argues here. Rather, we recognized that distinctions based on pregnancy are, in reality, sex-linked classifications. “[A]ny classification which relies on pregnancy as the determinative criterion is a distinction based on sex” because “it is the capacity to become pregnant which primarily differentiates the female from the male.” Bankers Life, 263 Mont. at 160, 866 P.2d at 243 (internal quotation marks omitted).

¶ 127 Likewise here, only different-sex couples have the capacity under current Montana law to get “married” and thereby become “spouses,” “husbands,” and “wives.” Same-sex couples are not permitted to marry and are thus categorically excluded from the statutory benefits and obligations granted to spouses, husbands, and wives. Mont. Const. art. XIII, § 7; §§ 40–1–103, –401(1)(d), MCA; Black's Law Dictionary 810, 1533, 1735 ( spouse: a married person; husband: a married man; wife: a married woman). Different-sex couples may obtain all of the benefits and obligations—by getting married. Same-sex couples may not obtain any of the benefits and obligations—because they cannot get married. Thus, while the classification may appear on its face to be marital status, the statutory definition of “spouse” is “[i]nherent” in this classification. Snetsinger, ¶ 20. And because marital status, by definition, is available only to different-sex couples, the pertinent classification is sexual orientation. Snetsinger, ¶ 27 (holding that sexual orientation, not marital status, is “the defining difference” where “unmarried opposite-sex couples are able to avail themselves of health benefits under the University System's policy while unmarried same-sex couples are denied the health benefits”).

¶ 128 Indeed, if the State limited marriage to Caucasians, and then granted an array of statutory benefits to such married couples, it would be ludicrous to argue—as the State does here—that “married couples qualify for spousal benefits not because they are [Caucasian] but because they are spouses.” This statement is simply wrong. Being Caucasian is, in fact, a prerequisite to qualifying for the benefits in this example, just as being heterosexual (or bisexual and committed to someone of the opposite sex) is a prerequisite to qualifying for the benefits in the present case. By granting benefits in a seemingly benign fashion to “spouses,” but then defining “spouses” to include only Caucasians, the relevant classification is race, not marital status. If the State limited the meaning of “spouse” to Catholics, the classification would be religious affiliation. And by defining “spouse” to mean a member of a different-sex couple, the statutory scheme creates a classification based on sexual orientation.

¶ 129 It is perplexing that the State is even making the contrary argument, given the multitude of courts that have already rejected it. In Tanner v. Oregon Health Sci. U., 157 Or.App. 502, 971 P.2d 435 (1998), for example, the governmental defendant argued that the benefits at issue were “available to all on equal terms” because “[a]ll married employees—heterosexual and homosexual alike—are permitted to acquire insurance benefits for their spouses.” 971 P.2d at 447–48 (emphasis omitted). As the Oregon Court of Appeals observed, such reasoning “misses the point”: “Homosexual couples may not marry. Accordingly, the benefits are not made available on equal terms. They are made available on terms that, for gay and lesbian couples, are a legal impossibility.” Tanner, 971 P.2d at 448. Similarly, the governmental defendants in Alaska Civ. Liberties Union argued that their programs differentiated on the basis of marital status, not sexual orientation. The Alaska Supreme Court, however, concluded otherwise:

We agree with the plaintiffs that the proper comparison is between same-sex couples and opposite-sex couples, whether or not they are married. The municipality correctly observes that no unmarried employees, whether they are members of same-sex or opposite-sex couples, can obtain the disputed benefits for their domestic partners. But this does not mean that these programs treat same-sex and opposite-sex couples the same. Unmarried public employees in opposite-sex domestic relationships have the opportunity to obtain these benefits, because employees are not prevented by law from marrying their opposite-sex domestic partners. In comparison, public employees in committed same-sex relationships are absolutely denied any opportunity to obtain these benefits, because these employees are barred by law from marrying their same-sex partners in Alaska or having any marriage performed elsewhere recognized in Alaska. Same-sex unmarried couples therefore have no way of obtaining these benefits, whereas opposite-sex unmarried couples may become eligible for them by marrying. The programs consequently treat same-sex couples differently from opposite-sex couples.
Alaska Civ. Liberties Union, 122 P.3d at 788;accord Collins v. Brewer, 727 F.Supp.2d 797, 803 (D.Ariz.2010), aff'd sub nom. Diaz v. Brewer, 656 F.3d 1008 (9th Cir.2011); Kerrigan v. Commr. of Pub. Health, 289 Conn. 135, 957 A.2d 407, 431 n. 24 (2008); Varnum, 763 N.W.2d at 883–84;Conaway v. Deane, 401 Md. 219, 932 A.2d 571, 605–06 (2007); Lewis v. Harris, 188 N.J. 415, 908 A.2d 196, 215 (2006); Hernandez v. Robles, 7 N.Y.3d 338, 821 N.Y.S.2d 770, 855 N.E.2d 1, 11 (2006); Baker, 744 A.2d at 880;cf. Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 583, 123 S.Ct. at 2486–87 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment) (“While it is true that the law applies only to conduct, the conduct targeted by this law is conduct that is closely correlated with being homosexual. Under such circumstances, Texas' sodomy law is targeted at more than conduct. It is instead directed toward gay persons as a class.”).

¶ 130 One of the fallacies in the State's approach is that it denies the most fundamental and defining aspect of same-sex relationships. The State contends that “[l]aws granting spousal benefits do not discriminate against gays and lesbians any more than they discriminate against ... other couples that may desire spousal benefits but do not qualify as spouses.” In other words, the State asserts, Plaintiffs “are situated no differently than unmarried different-sex partners.” Yet, as discussed above, different-sex partners may get married. And the State's implication that Plaintiffs may do the same—albeit, to someone of the opposite sex—is absurd. As the California Supreme Court explained:

By limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples, the marriage statutes, realistically viewed, operate clearly and directly to impose different treatment on gay individuals because of their sexual orientation. By definition, gay individuals are persons who are sexually attracted to persons of the same sex and thus, if inclined to enter into a marriage relationship, would choose to marry a person of their own sex or gender. A statute that limits marriage to a union of persons of opposite sexes, thereby placing marriage outside the reach of couples of the same sex, unquestionably imposes different treatment on the basis of sexual orientation. In our view, it is sophistic to suggest that this conclusion is avoidable by reason of the circumstance that the marriage statutes permit a gay man or a lesbian to marry someone of the opposite sex, because making such a choice would require the negation of the person's sexual orientation. Just as a statute that restricted marriage only to couples of the same sex would discriminate against heterosexual persons on the basis of their heterosexualorientation, the current California statutes realistically must be viewed as discriminating against gay persons on the basis of their homosexual orientation.
In re Marriage Cases, 43 Cal.4th 757, 76 Cal.Rptr.3d 683, 183 P.3d 384, 440–41 (2008) (emphasis added, footnote omitted). It should be noted that people have a constitutionally protected right under the “liberty” component of the Fourteenth Amendment's Due Process Clause and under the “privacy” provision of the Montana Constitution to choose a personal intimate relationship with someone of the same sex. Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 567, 123 S.Ct. at 2478;Gryczan, 283 Mont. at 455–56, 942 P.2d at 125–26. It is not the State's prerogative to prohibit such relationships. Nor, however, may the State seek to accomplish the same result through coercive measures—such as by denying homosexuals and bisexuals the equal protection of the State's secular laws when these individuals choose a partner of the same sex, rather than one of the opposite sex.

¶ 131 Another fallacy in the State's argument is the mistaken perception that “similarly situated” means “similar in the possession of the classifying trait.” When the government creates a particular classification, there of course will be some who fall within that class and some who fall outside of it. It is incorrect to say, however, as the State does here, that these two groups are not “similarly situated” because of the classification itself. Such circular reasoning would effectively immunize every classification against equal protection challenge. The Iowa Supreme Court discussed this point in Varnum:

In considering whether two classes are similarly situated, a court cannot simply look at the trait used by the legislature to define a classification under a statute and conclude a person without that trait is not similarly situated to persons with the trait. The equal protection clause does not merely ensure the challenged statute applies equally to all people in the legislative classification. “Similarly situated” cannot mean simply “similar in the possession of the classifying trait.” All members of any class are similarly situated in this respect and consequently, any classification whatsoever would be reasonable by this test. In the same way, the similarly situated requirement cannot possibly be interpreted to require plaintiffs to be identical in every way to people treated more favorably by the law. No two people or groups of people are the same in every way, and nearly every equal protection claim could be run aground onto the shoals of a threshold analysis if the two groups needed to be a mirror IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE


IMAGE

APPENDIX 2 to DISSENT


(Plaintiffs' Prayer for Relief)



PRAYER FOR RELIEF


WHEREFORE, Plaintiffs pray for:

(1) A declaration that the State's failure to offer same-sex couples equal opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations that are available to different-sex couples through the legal status of marriage violates Plaintiffs' right to equal protection under Article II, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution.

(2) A declaration that the State's exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who marry violates Plaintiffs' right to privacy under Article 11, Section 10 of the Montana Constitution.

(3) A declaration that the State's exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who marry violates Plaintiffs' right to dignity under Article 11, Section 4 of the Montana Constitution.

(4) A declaration that the State's exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who many violates Plaintiffs' right to pursue lie's basic necessities under Article 11, Section 3 of the Montana Constitution.

(5) A declaration that State's exclusion of same-sex couples from the opportunity to obtain the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who marry violates Plaintiffs' right to due process under Article 11, Section 17 of the Montana Constitution.

(6) An order enjoining the State from continuing to deny Plaintiffs and their families access to a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations the State provides to different-sex couples who marry.

(7) An order requiring the State to offer same-sex couples and their families a legal status and statutory structure that confers the protections and obligations that the State provides to different-sex couples who marry, but not the status or designation of marriage.

(8) An order awarding Plaintiffs their costs and their reasonable attorneys' fees.

(9) An order awarding such other and further relief as the Court deems just and proper.


Summaries of

Donaldson v. State

SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA
Dec 17, 2012
367 Mont. 228 (Mont. 2012)
Case details for

Donaldson v. State

Case Details

Full title:JAN DONALDSON and MARY ANNE GUGGENHEIM, MARY LESLIE and STACEY HAUGLAND…

Court:SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA

Date published: Dec 17, 2012

Citations

367 Mont. 228 (Mont. 2012)
292 P.3d 364
2012 MT 288

Citing Cases

Vision Net, Inc. v. State

'If the classes are not similarly situated, then . . . it is not necessary for us to analyze the challenge…

Mont. Indep. Living Project v. Mont. Dep't of Trans.

Such a presumption can only be overcome after careful consideration of the purpose and effect of the statute,…