From Casetext: Smarter Legal Research

United States v. Duvall

United States Court of Appeals FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT
Aug 13, 2013
740 F.3d 604 (D.C. Cir. 2013)

Summary

recognizing " Marks applies when the concurrence posits a narrow test to which the plurality must necessarily agree as a logical consequence of its own, broader position"

Summary of this case from In re Avery

Opinion

Nos. 10–3091 11–3114.

2013-08-13

UNITED STATES of America, Appellee v. David A. DUVALL, also known as Tone, Appellant.

Appeals from the United States District Court for the District of Columbia (No. 1:09–cr–00236–RCL–1). On Petition for Rehearing En Banc. Roy W. McLeese, III, Esquire, Assistant U.S., U.S. Attorney's Office, Washington, DC, for Appellee. Sylvia Royce, Law Office of Sylvia Royce, Washington, DC, for Appellant.


Appeals from the United States District Court for the District of Columbia (No. 1:09–cr–00236–RCL–1).
On Petition for Rehearing En Banc.
Roy W. McLeese, III, Esquire, Assistant U.S., U.S. Attorney's Office, Washington, DC, for Appellee. Sylvia Royce, Law Office of Sylvia Royce, Washington, DC, for Appellant.
Before GARLAND, Chief Judge; HENDERSON, ROGERS , TATEL, BROWN, GRIFFITH, KAVANAUGH , and SRINIVASAN , Circuit Judges; WILLIAMS

A statement by Circuit Judge Rogers concurring in the denial of the petition for rehearing en banc is attached.

A statement by Circuit Judge Kavanaugh concurring in the denial of the petition for rehearing en banc is attached.

Circuit Judge Srinivasan did not participate in this matter.

, Senior Circuit Judge.

A statement by Senior Circuit Judge Williams concurring in the denial of the petition for rehearing en banc is attached.

ORDER


PER CURIAM.

Upon consideration of appellant's petition for rehearing en banc, the response thereto, and the absence of a request by any member of the court for a vote, it is

ORDERED that the petition be denied.

ROGERS, Circuit Judge, concurring in the denial of rehearing en banc:

I write regarding Judge Kavanaugh's critique today of a related case, United States v. Epps, 707 F.3d 337 (D.C.Cir.2013). Our decision in Epps adhered to the interpretation of Marks v. United States, 430 U.S. 188, 97 S.Ct. 990, 51 L.Ed.2d 260 (1977), adopted by the en banc court in King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d 771 (D.C.Cir.1991), which is binding on the court. See LaShawn A. v. Barry, 87 F.3d 1389, 1395 (D.C.Cir.1996) (en banc). Any “seriously flawed application of the Marks principle,” Kavanaugh Op. at 609, if present, is thus to be found in King v. Palmer, not Epps. Critiquing Epps because “Marks means that, when one of the opinions in a splintered Supreme Court decision has adopted a legal standard that would consistently produce results with which a majority of the Court in that case necessarily would agree, that opinion controls,” Kavanaugh Op. at 606–07, is a direct challenge to King v. Palmer.

I.

As examined at length in Epps, 707 F.3d at 348–51,King v. Palmer precluded adoption of the interpretation of Marks followed in other circuits that have declared binding Justice Sotomayor's concurring opinion in the splintered decision in Freeman v. United States, ––– U.S. ––––, 131 S.Ct. 2685, 180 L.Ed.2d 519 (2011). In King v. Palmer, the en banc court interpreted Marks to mean that, to be binding as representing the narrowest grounds for decision, an opinion “must represent a common denominator of the Court's reasoning it must embody a position implicitly approved by at least five Justices who support the judgment.” 950 F.2d at 781 (emphasis added). Under Marks' “narrowest grounds” approach, for an opinion to be controlling it must contain a “controlling rationale.” Id. at 781 n. 6. “Marks is workable ... only when one opinion is a logical subset of other, broader opinions.” Id. at 781. Otherwise, the en banc court reasoned, “[i]f applied in situations where the various opinions supporting the judgment are mutually exclusive, Marks will turn a single opinion that lacks majority support into national law.” Id. at 782. So, “[w]hen ... one opinion supporting the judgment does not fit entirely within a broader circle drawn by the others, Marks is problematic.” Id. According to the en banc court, Marks applies when “the concurrence posits a narrow test to which the plurality must necessarily agree as a logical consequence of its own, broader position.” Id. (emphasis added); see also Epps, 707 F.3d at 348 (quoting same).

King v. Palmer expressed no ambivalence regarding either its general holding on the proper understanding of Marks ' “narrowest grounds” rule as requiring a binding opinion to evidence a common rationale and not only a common outcome, or its specific holding that, under its interpretation of Marks, in the absence of compatible reasoning by a majority in a splintered Supreme Court decision, “the appropriate course is to hold that contingency enhancements [to plaintiffs' counsel's award of attorneys' fees] will not be available in this circuit.” King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d at 784 (addressing the “splintered decision” in Pennsylvania v. Delaware Valley Citizens' Council for Clean Air, 483 U.S. 711, 107 S.Ct. 3078, 97 L.Ed.2d 585 (1987) ( “Delaware Valley II ”), and reversing this court's precedent in McKenzie v. Kennickell, 875 F.2d 330 (D.C.Cir.1989), and portions of previous inconsistent opinions). The en banc court emphasized that a concurring opinion widely assumed to be controlling due to the perceived presence of some sphere of outcome-determined “common ground” constituted only persuasive authority. Id. at 775–77. It identified “three distinct approaches to the issue of contingency enhancements in fee-shifting statutes, none of which enjoys the support of five Justices.” Id. at 782. Given that the Supreme Court had denied a contingency enhancement without a remand in Delaware Valley II, the court acknowledged that it “could not authorize the routine awarding of contingency enhancements of whatever size,” id. at 784, but determined there was no “narrowest opinion” to be derived from the plurality and concurring opinions because “there simply is no practical middle ground between providing enhancements routinely and not providing them at all,” id. Then, “[k]eeping in mind that a majority of the Supreme Court clearly agrees that the question of attorneys' fees must not turn into major litigation in itself,” the en banc court adopted its own view of “the appropriate course.” Id. (rejecting “various tests for awarding contingency enhancements” under Delaware Valley II adopted by the other circuits because “most of the tests appear to be difficult, if not impossible, to meet in practice”).

II.

Epps required the court to interpret a splintered Supreme Court decision to determine if a defendant sentenced pursuant to a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement was eligible for a sentencing reduction under 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2). Application of the Marks rule adopted in King v. Palmer to the Supreme Court's splintered 4–1–4 decision in Freeman revealed that Justice Sotomayor's concurring opinion cannot be understood to be the “narrowest grounds” of the majority's ruling, and therefore ought not be treated as controlling.

Epps explained: “The plurality opinion [in Freeman ] reject[ed] the concurring opinion's approach, stating its rationale is fundamentally incorrect because § 3582 (c)(2) ‘calls for an inquiry into the reasons for a judge's sentence, not the reasons that motivated or informed the parties.’ ” 707 F.3d at 350 (quoting Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2694 (plurality opinion) (labeling the concurrence's rationale an “erroneous rule”)). The dissenting opinion “agree [d] with the plurality that the approach of the concurrence ... is arbitrary and unworkable” and even “wrong.” Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2703 (dissent). In light of King v. Palmer, the only controlling holding evident from Freeman is that courts cannot categorically bar defendants sentenced pursuant to Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements from eligibility for a sentencing reduction under § 3582(c)(2). See Epps, 707 F.3d at 351.

In United States v. Duvall, by contrast, the court accepted the parties' stipulation that Justice Sotomayor's concurring opinion was controlling. 705 F.3d 479, 483 (D.C.Cir.2013).

Consequently, the Epps court had to determine, as the en banc court instructed, which reasoning represented “the appropriate course,” King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d at 784. The Freeman plurality had observed that “the statute ... calls for an inquiry into the reasons for a judge's sentence, not the reasons that motivated or informed the parties,” and that the concurrence, “[b]y allowing modification only where the terms of the agreement contemplate it ... would permit the very disparities that the Sentencing Reform Act seeks to eliminate.” Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2694. The Freeman dissent, on the other hand, despaired of being able to determine, where a judge approved the parties' agreed-upon fixed-term sentence under Rule 11(c)(1)(C), what the sentence was “based on,” id. at 2703 (dissent) (quoting § 3582(c)(2)), a circumstance not present in Epps, 707 F.3d at 352 (citing United States v. Epps, 756 F.Supp.2d 88, 92–93 (D.D.C.2010)). This court adhered to the plurality's interpretation in view of the purpose of the Sentencing Act to reduce unwarranted disparities, Rule 11(c)(1)(C)'s requirement that the sentencing judge approve the plea agreement, and instructions in applicable Sentencing Guidelines policy statements. Epps, 707 F.3d at 351–53. (The third member of the panel concluded the issue of Epps' entitlement to sentencing relief was moot. Id. at 353 (Brown, J., dissenting)). In so doing, Epps also followed the approach adopted in United States v. Berry, 618 F.3d 13 (D.C.Cir.2010), where this court relied on the Guidelines policy statement 1B1.10, which the Freeman plurality explained “seeks to isolate whatever marginal effect the since-rejected Guidelines had on the defendant's sentence,” thereby “permitting the district court to revisit a prior sentence to whatever extent the sentencing range ... was a relevant part of the analytic framework the judge used to determine the sentence or to approve the [Rule 11(c)(1)(C)] agreement.” 131 S.Ct. at 2692–93.

The three asserted errors in Epps are non-existent: First, Epps did not adopt “a novel standard for Marks cases.” Kavanaugh Op. at 612. Instead, the court correctly concluded that “[u]nder Marks [as interpreted in King v. Palmer] ... there is no controlling opinion in Freeman because the plurality and concurring opinions do not share common reasoning whereby one analysis is a ‘logical subset,’ King, 950 F.2d at 781, of the other.” Epps, 707 F.3d at 350 (emphasis added for text omitted by Judge Kavanaugh).

Second, a suggestion in the concurring opinion in United States v. Duvall, 705 F.3d 479 (D.C.Cir.2013), regarding possible “ weak” or “strong” readings of King v. Palmer, see Duvall, 705 F.3d at 485–86 (Williams, J., concurring), cannot change the en banc court's unambiguous holding on the proper interpretation of Marks' “narrowest grounds.” See Kavanaugh Op. at 614. Nevertheless, Epps addressed the suggested “weak reading,” anticipatorily explaining why the concurring opinion in Freeman still would not be deemed controlling. The court referred under the “weak” reading to the circumstance (as contemplated by the plurality in Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2694) in which the concurrence in Freeman would grant relief and the plurality would not. See Epps, 707 F.3d at 350–51 & n. 8. Other courts appear not to have considered this circumstance, see, e.g., United States v. Rivera–Martinez, 665 F.3d 344, 348 (1st Cir. 2011); see also In re Sealed Case, 722 F.3d 361, 365–66 (D.C.Cir.2013) (dictum).

Third, Epps did not “misappl[y] the ‘Marks corollary’ that necessarily governs in cases where there is no one narrowest opinion.” Kavanaugh Op. at 616. As described by Judge Kavanaugh, that corollary requires a court to “run the facts and circumstances of the current case through the various tests articulated by the Supreme Court in the binding case.” Id. at 616. Whatever its merits, the en banc court never endorsed this corollary to Marks, but adhered to its “subset” analysis. King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d at 784 & n. 7;see also id. at 781–82. None of the Supreme Court cases cited by Judge Kavanaugh in discussing vertical stare decisis, Kavanaugh Op. at 611–12, includes a binding instruction adopting his Marks corollary.

So, this court must follow the approach adopted by the en banc court—identifying “the appropriate course,” King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d at 784—which Epps identified in terms of the undisputed purpose of the Sentencing Reform Act, the plain texts of Rule 11(c)(1)(C) and the Sentencing Guidelines policy, and our own § 3582(c)(2) precedent relying on the policy statement.

In O'Dell v. J.D. Netherland, 521 U.S. 151, 117 S.Ct. 1969, 138 L.Ed.2d 351 (1997), see Kavanaugh Op. at 612–13, a capital case, the Supreme Court discussed another capital case, Gardner v. Florida, 430 U.S. 349, 97 S.Ct. 1197, 51 L.Ed.2d 393 (1977), in which the concurring opinion appears to be consistent with King v. Palmer 's “subset” interpretation of the Marks rule. See O'Dell, 521 U.S. at 174–75, 117 S.Ct. 1969 (dissent) (pointing out that the Gardner opinion identified in O'Dell as “the narrow one” embraced the due process rationale of the Gardner plurality).

Properly understood, Judge Kavanaugh's objection is to the interpretation of Marks adopted by the en banc court in King v. Palmer. In disagreeing with the result in Epps, he revives objections reminiscent of the dissent in King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d at 789 (dissent), but the three-judge panel in Epps was not free to agree with this position. Judge Williams, concurring in the denial of en banc in Duvall, elaborates on why Judge Kavanaugh's criticism of the en banc court's interpretation of Marks may lack traction and rebuts his criticisms of Epps. Regardless, because the en banc decision in King v. Palmer is binding, the suggestion that the court in Epps acted other than consistently with its constitutional obligation is without merit.

KAVANAUGH, Circuit Judge, concurring in the denial of rehearing en banc:

When the Supreme Court issues a splintered decision—that is, a decision where a majority of the Court agrees on the result but not the reasoning—the binding holding is the position taken by those Justices “who concurred in the judgment[ ] on the narrowest grounds.” Marks v. United States, 430 U.S. 188, 193, 97 S.Ct. 990, 51 L.Ed.2d 260 (1977). Under the Marks principle, when one of the opinions in a splintered Supreme Court decision has adopted a legal standard that would produce results with which a majority of the Court in that case necessarily would agree, that opinion controls.

In a recent case, Freeman v. United States, the Supreme Court splintered over whether a defendant who enters into a binding Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement specifying an agreed-upon sentence is eligible for a sentence reduction after the Guidelines sentencing range for the offense has been retroactively reduced. ––– U.S. ––––, 131 S.Ct. 2685, 180 L.Ed.2d 519 (2011). Under the governing statute, defendants are eligible for a sentence reduction if, among other things, they were sentenced “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range that was later lowered by the Sentencing Commission. See18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2).

In an opinion by Justice Kennedy, a four-Justice plurality of the Freeman Court reasoned that sentences in cases with Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements are always “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range because the Judge's decision to accept such plea agreements is framed by the Guidelines. Thus, in the plurality's view, those defendants are always eligible for a sentence reduction when the applicable Guidelines sentencing range has been retroactively reduced. In an opinion by Chief Justice Roberts, a four-Justice dissent reasoned that sentences in cases with Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements are never “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range because those sentences are based on the plea agreement, not on the Guidelines. Thus, in the dissent's view, those defendants are never eligible for a sentence reduction.

Justice Sotomayor, alone concurring in the judgment, adopted a middle ground in Freeman. She reasoned that sentences in cases with Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements are sometimes “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range—namely, when the plea agreement itself makes clear that the basis for the specified sentence is a Guidelines sentencing range. Thus, in those circumstances, defendants are eligible for a sentence reduction when the applicable Guidelines sentencing range has been retroactively reduced.

The question at issue in this appeal is which opinion is the binding opinion in Freeman. The answer should be obvious. Justice Sotomayor's opinion resolved the case on the narrowest grounds and is therefore the binding opinion in Freeman. Adhering to her opinion would produce results with which a majority of the Freeman Court would agree. Not surprisingly, every other court of appeals to consider the question has therefore determined that Justice Sotomayor's opinion is the binding opinion. See United States v. Rivera–Martínez, 665 F.3d 344, 347–48 (1st Cir.2011); United States v. White, 429 Fed.Appx. 43, 47 (2d Cir.2011) (unpublished); United States v. Thompson, 682 F.3d 285, 289–90 (3d Cir.2012); United States v. Brown, 653 F.3d 337, 340 & n. 1 (4th Cir.2011); United States v. Smith, 658 F.3d 608, 611 (6th Cir.2011); United States v. Dixon, 687 F.3d 356, 359–60 (7th Cir.2012); United States v. Browne, 698 F.3d 1042, 1045 (8th Cir.2012); United States v. Austin, 676 F.3d 924, 927 (9th Cir.2012); United States v. Graham, 704 F.3d 1275, 1278 (10th Cir.2013); United States v. Lawson, 686 F.3d 1317, 1321 n. 2 (11th Cir.2012). Indeed, in Freeman itself, Justice Kennedy's plurality opinion for four Justices referred to Justice Sotomayor's position as the “intermediate position.” 131 S.Ct. at 2694 (opinion of Kennedy, J.). And Chief Justice Roberts's dissent for four Justices likewise treated Justice Sotomayor's opinion as binding. See id. at 2700–05 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting). And in United States v. Duvall, a panel of this Court similarly assumed as much, as did both the Government and the defendant in that case. 705 F.3d 479 (D.C.Cir.2013).

But then in United States v. Epps, a separate panel of this Court adopted Justice Kennedy's plurality opinion in Freeman. United States v. Epps, 707 F.3d 337, 350–51 (D.C.Cir.2013). Epps means that courts in this Circuit often will find that a sentence was “based on” the Guidelines (and thus the defendant is eligible for a sentencing reduction) even when the sentence indisputably was not “based on” the Guidelines under the approaches adopted by a majority of the Freeman Court—namely, under the opinions of Justice Sotomayor and Chief Justice Roberts. Indeed, Epps himself would have lost under the approaches adopted by a majority of the Supreme Court in Freeman. Under the opinions of Justice Sotomayor and Chief Justice Roberts, Epps's plea agreement indisputably was not “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range.

I find Epps to be a seriously flawed application of the Marks principle. The Epps decision puts us out of step with every other court of appeals that has considered Freeman and, more fundamentally, will lead to results in many cases with which a majority of the Supreme Court in Freeman would necessarily disagree. The point of Marks, however, is for lower courts to reach results with which a majority of the Supreme Court in the relevant precedent would agree.

In his en banc petition here, Duvall understandably seeks to reap the benefit of the Epps ruling. I am voting to deny the petition because the problem is Epps, not Duvall, and we should await an en banc petition that asks us to reconsider Epps. If we receive such a petition, we should grant it and overturn Epps so as to follow Justice Sotomayor's binding opinion in Freeman and bring our case law into line with every other court of appeals that has considered the question.

I

Vertical stare decisis is absolute and requires lower courts to follow applicable Supreme Court rulings in every case. The Constitution vests Judicial Power in only one Supreme Court. U.S. Const. art. III, § 1. We are subordinate to that one Supreme Court, and we must decide cases in line with Supreme Court precedent.

Vertical stare decisis applies to Supreme Court precedent in two ways. First, the result in a given Supreme Court case binds all lower courts. Second, the reasoning of a Supreme Court case also binds lower courts. So once a rule, test, standard, or interpretation has been adopted by the Supreme Court, that same rule, test, standard, or interpretation must be used by lower courts in later cases. See, e.g., Seminole Tribe of Florida v. Florida, 517 U.S. 44, 67, 116 S.Ct. 1114, 134 L.Ed.2d 252 (1996) (“When an opinion issues for the Court, it is not only the result but also those portions of the opinion necessary to that result by which we are bound.”); see also Randall v. Sorrell, 548 U.S. 230, 243, 126 S.Ct. 2479, 165 L.Ed.2d 482 (2006) (opinion of Breyer, J.) (stare decisis “commands judicial respect for a court's earlier decisions and the rules of law they embody”); County of Allegheny v. American Civil Liberties Union, Greater Pittsburgh Chapter, 492 U.S. 573, 668, 109 S.Ct. 3086, 106 L.Ed.2d 472 (1989) (separate opinion of Kennedy, J.) (“As a general rule, the principle of stare decisis directs us to adhere not only to the holdings of our prior cases, but also to their explications of the governing rules of law.”).

In most cases, at least five Justices of the Supreme Court join a single majority opinion that agrees on both the result and the reasoning. Justices who join the majority may of course express additional thoughts in a concurrence, but concurrences do not bind lower courts in cases where there is a majority opinion.

In some cases, however, no single opinion commands majority support, even though five or more Justices agree on a result. In those cases, there will be two or more opinions supporting the judgment of the Court, without any one opinion commanding a majority. For much of the Court's history, the precedential value of such splintered decisions was unclear. See Justin Marceau, Plurality Decisions: Upward–Flowing Precedent and Acoustic Separation, 45 Conn. L.Rev. 933, 948–49 (2013); Joseph M. Cacace, Note, Plurality Decisions in the Supreme Court of the United States: A Reexamination of the Marks Doctrine After Rapanos v. United States, 41 Suffolk U.L.Rev. 97, 104–05 (2007).

In Marks v. United States, the Supreme Court furnished important guidance regarding the stare decisis value of splintered decisions. 430 U.S. 188, 97 S.Ct. 990, 51 L.Ed.2d 260 (1977). There, the Court articulated a commonsense test to determine which opinion (for example, a plurality opinion or an opinion concurring in the judgment) is the binding opinion in a splintered decision: “When a fragmented Court decides a case and no single rationale explaining the result enjoys the assent of five Justices, the holding of the Court may be viewed as that position taken by those Members who concurred in the judgments on the narrowest grounds....” Id. at 193, 97 S.Ct. 990 (internal quotation marks omitted).

Marks means that, when one of the opinions in a splintered Supreme Court decision has adopted a legal standard that would produce results with which a majority of the Court in that case necessarily would agree, that opinion controls. In most cases, the commonsense way to apply Marks is to identify and follow the opinion that occupies the middle ground between (i) the broader opinion supporting the judgment and (ii) the dissenting opinion. That middle-ground opinion will produce results that represent a subset of the results generated by the other opinions. By applying that approach, lower courts will decide cases consistently with the opinions of a majority of the Supreme Court in the relevant precedent. See, e.g., O'Dell v. Netherland, 521 U.S. 151, 160, 117 S.Ct. 1969, 138 L.Ed.2d 351 (1997) (adopting opinion from Gardner v. Florida, 430 U.S. 349, 97 S.Ct. 1197, 51 L.Ed.2d 393 (1977), that predicts majority result even when Justices in prior precedent had based reasoning on different constitutional amendments); Dickens v. Brewer, 631 F.3d 1139, 1145 (9th Cir.2011) (“When applying the Marks rule, we look for a legal standard which, when applied, will necessarily produce results with which a majority of the Justices from that case would agree.”) (internal quotation marks and brackets omitted); Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 947 F.2d 682, 693 (3d Cir.1991) (“Where a Justice or Justices concurring in the judgment in such a case articulates a legal standard which, when applied, will necessarily produce results with which a majority of the Court from that case would agree, that standard is the law of the land.”); King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d 771, 781 (D.C.Cir.1991) (narrowest opinion must be “logical subset of other, broader opinions” and “must represent a common denominator of the Court's reasoning; it must embody a position implicitly approved by at least five Justices who support the judgment”) (emphasis added).

The Marks rule is an essential aspect of vertical stare decisis: “The binding opinion from a splintered decision is as authoritative for lower courts as a nine-Justice opinion. While the opinion's symbolic and perceived authority, as well as its duration, may be less, that makes no difference for a lower court. This is true even if only one Justice issues the binding opinion.” Planned Parenthood, 947 F.2d at 694.

To be clear, the goal for a lower court under Marks is not to speculate or predict how a future Supreme Court might decide a case. The goal is to determine how the principles set forth by the Supreme Court in a prior decision would apply to the current case facing the lower court. Thus, Judge Williams is incorrect to suggest that I would require lower courts to predict future Supreme Court action. See Williams Op. at 623.

In interpreting most splintered Supreme Court decisions, the Marks rule is not especially complicated. But on rare occasions, splintered decisions have no “narrowest” opinion that would identify how a majority of the Supreme Court would resolve all future cases. Marks itself did not have reason to specifically address that situation. But in that situation, the necessary logical corollary to Marks is that lower courts should still strive to decide the case before them in a way consistent with how the Supreme Court's opinions in the relevant precedent would resolve the current case. See King, 950 F.2d at 784 (confronting this circumstance and stating that when a decision “provides no controlling legal holding,” it nevertheless has “binding impact”); see, e.g., Nichols v. United States, 511 U.S. 738, 114 S.Ct. 1921, 128 L.Ed.2d 745 (1994). The easy way to do that is for the lower court to run the facts and circumstances of the current case through the tests articulated in the Justices' various opinions in the binding case and adopt the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached. See, e.g., Bobby v. Dixon, ––– U.S. ––––, 132 S.Ct. 26, 31–32, 181 L.Ed.2d 328 (2011) (reaching result that plurality and concurring opinion from relevant precedent would reach); City of Ontario v. Quon, 560 U.S. 746, 130 S.Ct. 2619, 2629, 177 L.Ed.2d 216 (2010) (reaching result when two “approaches—the plurality's and Justice Scalia's ... lead to the same result”); Rapanos v. United States, 547 U.S. 715, 758, 126 S.Ct. 2208, 165 L.Ed.2d 159 (2006) (Roberts, C.J., concurring) (cases with no controlling opinion like Rapanos have to be interpreted on a “case-by-case basis”); id. at 810, 126 S.Ct. 2208 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (when at least five Justices—the dissent plus either the plurality or concurrence—would reach a given result, then lower courts should reach that result).

When the Supreme Court itself applies Marks, it is not bound in the same way that lower courts are bound by Marks to strictly follow the narrowest opinion from a prior splintered Supreme Court decision. That's because the Supreme Court is free to reconsider or refine or tweak its own precedents—including splintered precedents—and it does so in appropriate cases. Lower courts, by contrast, are not free to reconsider or refine or tweak Supreme Court precedents. Marks is therefore even more important at the lower court level.

Indeed, if a lower court ever has doubt about the predictive utility of a single opinion from a splintered Supreme Court decision, this opinion-by-opinion methodology is a foolproof way to reach the correct result in the lower court's subsequent decisions. Again, that is really just common sense in a system of absolute vertical stare decisis.

II

Now back to Freeman. Applying the Marks rule to Freeman is fairly easy, which no doubt explains why every other court of appeals has reached the same conclusion: Justice Sotomayor's Freeman opinion is the binding opinion from that case.

In Freeman, the Supreme Court considered whether a defendant who entered into a binding Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement specifying an agreed-upon sentence was eligible for a sentence reduction after the relevant Guidelines sentencing range for the offense had been retroactively reduced. Federal law permits a sentence reduction when a defendant “has been sentenced to a term of imprisonment based on a sentencing range that has subsequently been lowered by the Sentencing Commission.” 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2) (emphasis added). The key question in Freeman was whether the sentence in a case involving a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement is “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range.

In a plurality opinion written by Justice Kennedy, a group of four Justices concluded that sentences in cases with Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements are always “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range, because “the court's acceptance” of the plea agreement must itself be “based on the Guidelines.” Freeman v. United States, ––– U.S. ––––, 131 S.Ct. 2685, 2692, 180 L.Ed.2d 519 (2011) (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (citing U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 6B1.2); see id. at 2690–95. Another group of four Justices, in a dissent written by Chief Justice Roberts, concluded that Rule 11(c)(1)(C) sentences are never based on a Guidelines sentencing range, because the sentences are “based on” the plea agreement itself rather than on the Guidelines. See id. at 2700–05 (Roberts, C.J., dissenting). And Justice Sotomayor, who concurred in the judgment alone, concluded that Rule 11(c)(1)(C) sentences are sometimes “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range. See id. at 2695–700 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.). Justice Sotomayor explained that sentences in Rule 11(c)(1)(C) cases are “based on” the plea agreements, but some such plea agreements are in turn “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range, whereas other Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreements are not. Under Justice Sotomayor's theory, the sentence in a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) case is “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range if the plea agreement makes “clear that the basis for the specified term is a Guidelines sentencing range.” Id. at 2697.

Following Justice Sotomayor's opinion with regard to the “based on” issue would produce results with which a majority of the Supreme Court in Freeman would agree because—to put it in simple terms—“sometimes” is a middle ground between “always” and “never.” In other words, when Justice Sotomayor concludes that a plea agreement was based on the Guidelines, she would agree with the result reached under Justice Kennedy's opinion for four Justices. When she concludes that a plea agreement was not based on the Guidelines, she would agree with the result reached under Chief Justice Roberts's opinion for four Justices. But unlike every other court of appeals, Epps did not follow this commonsense approach to interpreting Freeman.

As I see it, Epps erred in several independent ways.

First, the Epps panel articulated a novel standard for applying Marks to splintered Supreme Court decisions: If the Supreme Court opinions in the majority do not share a “common rationale,” then there is no binding opinion for lower courts to follow, even if applying one of the opinions would produce results with which a majority of the Supreme Court would agree. United States v. Epps, 707 F.3d 337, 349 (D.C.Cir.2013).

But Marks does not require the multiple opinions supporting the Supreme Court's judgment to employ a “common rationale.” After all, in splintered cases, there are multiple opinions precisely because the Justices did not agree on a common rationale. See, e.g., O'Dell v. Netherland, 521 U.S. 151, 160, 117 S.Ct. 1969, 138 L.Ed.2d 351 (1997) (adopting controlling opinion from Gardner v. Florida, 430 U.S. 349, 97 S.Ct. 1197, 51 L.Ed.2d 393 (1977), despite the fact that plurality and concurrences based reasoning on different constitutional amendments); Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 169 n. 15, 96 S.Ct. 2909, 49 L.Ed.2d 859 (1976) (opinion of Stewart, Powell, and Stevens, JJ.) (recognizing opinions of Justices Stewart and White as controlling from Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 92 S.Ct. 2726, 33 L.Ed.2d 346 (1972), even though their opinions did not employ common rationale with all other members of majority). Even though it is often not possible to identify a “common rationale” in the multiple opinions from a splintered decision, lower courts can still reach a result consistent with the opinions of a majority of the Supreme Court. They can do so by following the opinion that would lead to an outcome that a majority of the Supreme Court in the governing precedent would have reached if confronted with the current case.

WITH RESPECT TO freeman and the “based on” issue, justice Sotomayor's opinion does just that, as every other court of appeals has recognized.

The joint Epps opinion by Judges Rogers and Williams cited this Court's precedent in King v. Palmer as support for Epps 's “common rationale” principle. See Epps, 707 F.3d 337;King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d 771 (D.C.Cir.1991). But King v. Palmer does not require that the opinions forming a majority share a “common rationale” in order for Marks to apply. In his Duvall concurrence, Judge Williams explained his view that King v. Palmer is susceptible to either a “weak” or “strong” reading. United States v. Duvall, 705 F.3d 479, 485 (D.C.Cir.2013) (Williams, J., concurring in the judgment). Under the so-called weak reading of King, the controlling opinion in a splintered decision is the opinion that predicts a result with which a majority of the Supreme Court from the relevant precedent would agree. See id. at 487 (reading “would seem to require only that as a purely factual matter cases producing an outcome in favor of the defendant under Justice Sotomayor's opinion would invariably yield an outcome in his favor under the plurality view”). The strong reading of King would find an opinion binding only if the opinion has a “common rationale” with the other opinions necessary to form a majority. I believe what Judge Williams described as the weak reading of King is most consistent with Marks and with King itself. Indeed, that reading of King must be correct because, among other things, King identified the opinions of Justices Stewart and White in Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 92 S.Ct. 2726, 33 L.Ed.2d 346, as the narrowest opinions in Furman. King, 950 F.2d at 781. There were five separate opinions for the Justices in the majority in Furman, and none of those five Justices joined any of the others' opinions. Those five opinions certainly did not have a “common rationale.” The opinions of Justices Stewart and White were binding because they would produce results in future cases with which a majority of the Court in Furman would agree.
Judge Rogers and Judge Williams thus are not correct in suggesting that I disagree with King on this point. Rather, of the two plausible readings of King that Judge Williams previously identified in his Duvall concurrence, I simply believe the weak reading of King to be more consistent with Marks.

Judge Williams's opinion respecting the denial of en banc essentially collapses the Epps “common rationale” standard into the requirement that lower courts follow the opinion that would lead to a result that a majority of the Supreme Court would reach. If so, then my disagreement with Judge Williams relates only to the second and third points discussed in the text of my opinion here. That is not, however, how the Epps opinion itself appeared to describe its “common rationale” standard.

Second, Epps suggested (apparently in the alternative) that, even if the Marks rule focuses on identifying the opinion that would achieve results with which a majority of the Supreme Court would agree and does not depend on whether there was a “common rationale” among the opinions making up the Supreme Court majority, Freeman has no narrowest opinion that would always lead to the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would reach in future cases. Epps hypothesized a situation where Justice Sotomayor, despite taking the middle ground, would supposedly disagree with both Justice Kennedy's four-Justice plurality opinion and Chief Justice Roberts's four-Justice dissenting opinion. See Epps, 707 F.3d at 350 n. 8. As Justice Kennedy's plurality opinion stated, however, the sole question resolved by Freeman was “whether defendants who enter into 11(c)(1)(C) agreements that specify a particular sentence may be said to have been sentenced ‘based on ’ a Guidelines sentencing range, making them eligible for relief under § 3582(c)(2).” Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2691 (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (emphasis added). And on the question whether a defendant's sentence was “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range, there is no circumstance where Justice Sotomayor would reach a result different from all of the other eight Justices. Given Justice Sotomayor's conclusion that the sentences for Rule 11(c)(1)(C) defendants are sometimes “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range, Justice Sotomayor's conclusion would necessarily coincide in any given case with either the plurality's conclusion (which determined that such sentences are always “based on” the Guidelines) or with the dissent's conclusion (which determined that such sentences are never “based on” the Guidelines).

So under Marks, Justice Sotomayor's opinion is binding with respect to the “based on” question.

Epps suggested that Justice Kennedy's plurality opinion may not always find a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement to be “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range. That is incorrect. The Freeman plurality determined that “if the judge uses the sentencing range as the beginning point” when imposing the sentence, “then the Guidelines are in a real sense a basis for the sentence.” 131 S.Ct. at 2692 (opinion of Kennedy, J.). And district court judges are required to calculate the Guidelines sentencing range as their beginning point before imposing a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) sentence. SeeU.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 6B1.2(c). So under the plurality approach, a sentence in a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) case will always be “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range. Indeed, this Court recently said just that about Justice Kennedy's plurality opinion. See In re Sealed Case, 722 F.3d at 363 (D.C.Cir.2013). In Sealed Case, we stated: Using Justice Kennedy's plurality approach, “a sentence that emerges from a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement is always eligible for a subsequent reduction because ‘[t]he Guidelines require the district judge to give due consideration to the relevant sentencing range, even if the defendant and prosecutor recommend a specific sentence as a condition of the guilty plea.’ ” Id. (quoting Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2692 (opinion of Kennedy, J.)) (emphasis added); see also United States v. Brown, 653 F.3d 337, 339 (4th Cir.2011) (under plurality approach, “a district court can always grant § 3582(c)(2) relief to a defendant who enters into a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) plea agreement”) (emphasis added); United States v. Rivera–Martínez, 665 F.3d 344, 347 (1st Cir.2011) (“Even in cases in which sentencing follows the execution of a C-type plea agreement, the sentencing judge is required to take the guidelines into account when deciding whether to accept the agreement and impose the agreed sentence.”).

Epps premised its conclusion that Justice Sotomayor's opinion was not the narrowest on the idea that Justice Sotomayor would allow a sentencing reduction in certain Rule 11(c)(1)(C) cases involving career offenders and offenders subject to a mandatory minimum, whereas (according to Epps ) none of the other eight Justices supposedly would. That is, moving beyond the “based on” question, Epps claimed that Justice Sotomayor would reach a different conclusion than the other eight Justices on the question whether defendants in cases involving career offenders and offenders subject to a mandatory minimum are ultimately eligible for a sentence reduction under Section 3582(c)(2). But in those cases, Justice Sotomayor would not allow a sentence reduction; indeed, no Justice would.

To explain: To obtain a sentencing reduction under Section 3582(c)(2), the defendant not only must show that the sentence was “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range, but also must meet an additional requirement. The defendant must show that the “ applicable guideline range” was subsequently lowered. U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 1B1.10(a)(2)(B) (emphasis added); see18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2) (sentence revision must be “consistent with applicable policy statements issued by the Sentencing Commission”). In cases where a defendant's applicable Guidelines sentencing range involves a career offender or mandatory minimum provision, the fact that the Guidelines sentencing range for the offense of conviction—for example, a crack-cocaine Guideline—was later lowered would not alone suffice to support a Section 3582(c)(2) sentencing reduction. That is because, in cases involving a career offender or defendant subject to a mandatory minimum, the “applicable” Guidelines sentencing range is the range for career offenders or offenders subject to a mandatory minimum. And in such a case, that Guidelines sentencing range would not have been lowered even if, say, the relevant crack-cocaine Guideline had been lowered. In those circumstances, none of the opinions in Freeman—not Justice Kennedy's opinion, not Justice Sotomayor's opinion, not Chief Justice Roberts's opinion—would support a Section 3582(c)(2) reduction.

Indeed, the Sentencing Commission has made clear that a reduction is not available in those cases. The Application Note to Section 1B1.10 of the Guidelines, which governs sentence reductions, specifically states that a defendant may not obtain a sentence reduction if “the amendment does not have the effect of lowering the defendant's applicable guideline range because of the operation of another guideline or statutory provision (e.g., a statutory mandatory minimum term of imprisonment).” U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual § 1B1.10, Application Note 1(A); see id., amend. 759 (effective Nov. 1, 2011) (defining the term “applicable guideline range”).

Notwithstanding the language of Guidelines Section 1B1.10, Epps premised its conclusion that Justice Sotomayor's Freeman opinion is not the narrowest opinion on the notion that Justice Sotomayor—alone among the Freeman Justices— would allow a sentence reduction for career offenders and offenders subject to a mandatory minimum, supposedly because the plea agreement itself would not have rested on the career offender or mandatory minimum range. The Epps Court's assessment of Justice Sotomayor's opinion thus necessarily presupposes that she would ignore the separate Guidelines requirement (which is binding on federal courts) that the applicable Guidelines range, which in those circumstances would be a career offender or mandatory minimum provision, must also be lowered in order for a defendant to be eligible for a sentence reduction. Unlike the Epps panel, I see no basis for thinking that Justice Sotomayor would ignore that Guidelines requirement.

Moreover, the Epps premise also ignores this Court's decision in Berry, where we already held that a Section 3582(c)(2) sentencing reduction is not available when the applicable Guidelines sentencing range has not been lowered because of the operation of a career offender or mandatory minimum provision. See United States v. Berry, 618 F.3d 13 (D.C.Cir.2010). Notably, in Duvall, Judge Williams specifically called for the en banc court to overrule Berry. Judge Williams's desire to overrule Berry becomes understandable when one appreciates that the premise of Epps—namely, that Justice Sotomayor would still grant relief in career offender or mandatory minimum cases—all but collapses so long as Berry is still on the books. However, not only is Berry still on the books, but as I noted in the text, the Sentencing Commission has made clear that Berry is correct and that a sentencing reduction under Section 3582(c)(2) is not appropriate in those circumstances.

So contrary to Epps 's assertion, Justice Sotomayor's opinion would not reach a different result than Justice Kennedy's opinion or Chief Justice Roberts's opinion in those career offender or mandatory minimum circumstances. Thus, the hypothetical situation that Epps identifies as the basis for not following Justice Sotomayor's opinion simply does not exist.

Third, despite all that, let's suppose that I am wrong so far and that, indeed, there was no narrowest opinion in Freeman that governs all future cases. In other words, suppose that Epps is right that Justice Sotomayor's opinion would allow a sentencing reduction under Section 3582(c)(2) in some circumstances where the other eight Justices would not. Even accepting that premise, Epps misapplied the Marks corollary that necessarily governs in cases where there is no narrowest opinion: In such cases, the lower court should still strive to reach the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached under the opinions in the governing precedent.

Epps said that lower courts analyzing a splintered decision with no narrowest opinion may unilaterally adopt any of the Justices' opinions that supported the Supreme Court's judgment—even an opinion at the extreme end of the spectrum—and apply that one opinion in all future cases. See Epps, 707 F.3d at 349–51.Epps thus leads to an extraordinary situation in which lower courts in all subsequent cases may follow a broader opinion supporting the judgment and, by doing so, decide future cases differently than a majority of the Supreme Court in the governing precedent would decide the cases. Consider the logic Epps employs: Because Justice Sotomayor's approach would allegedly lead to relief in some small subset of Section 3582(c)(2) cases where the other eight Justices would deny relief, lower courts should follow Justice Kennedy's broader approach in all cases, even though a majority of the Supreme Court would definitely disagree with the result achieved under Justice Kennedy's approach in many if not most of those cases. The logic behind Epps eludes me.

The core of the Marks principle cannot be sidestepped simply because the multiple opinions supporting the Supreme Court's judgment did not produce a single narrowest opinion for all future cases. As explained above, in those rare no-narrowest-opinion cases, the lower court still must strive to reach the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached in the current case, if such a result can be ascertained. The simplest way to do that, again, is to run the facts and circumstances of the current case through the various tests articulated by the Supreme Court in the binding case. Using that approach, lower courts can still reach a result consistent with the decision of a majority of the Supreme Court. That is what Marks, common sense, and vertical stare decisis all require.

Judge Rogers says that the Marks corollary is inconsistent with this Court's decision in King v. Palmer. I disagree. As I read King, the core of the problem there was that the en banc Court simply could not decipher Justice O'Connor's opinion in Delaware Valley II, the Supreme Court precedent at issue. See King, 950 F.2d at 782 (Justice O'Connor's “concurrence does not contain enough independent reasoning on the question of availability to allow us to compare her position analytically to that of the plurality.”); see also City of Burlington v. Dague, 505 U.S. 557, 563, 112 S.Ct. 2638, 120 L.Ed.2d 449 (1992) (overruling Delaware Valley II on the ground that “we do not see how” Justice O'Connor's Delaware Valley II concurrence “can intelligibly be applied”). As the Supreme Court itself later concluded, it was essentially impossible to know how Justice O'Connor's opinion would sensibly apply to the situation presented in King (or in any other situation). Indeed, King compared Justice O'Connor's opinion in Delaware Valley II to Justice Harlan's opinion in Coolidge v. New Hampshire, 403 U.S. 443, 91 S.Ct. 2022, 29 L.Ed.2d 564 (1971), which the King Court described as having “no reasoning by which one could discern his position” on the legal question at issue. 950 F.2d at 782. Here, by contrast, we can readily discern Justice Sotomayor's reasoning and what result Justice Sotomayor would reach in Epps's case.

So even if one mistakenly thinks that Freeman itself has no binding opinion that governs all future cases—as Epps said about Freeman—the solution still would not be to rule for Epps in his case. After all, Epps would lose under the approaches adopted by five Justices in Freeman: Justice Sotomayor's opinion and Chief Justice Roberts's opinion for four additional Justices. Under the opinions of those five Justices, Epps's plea agreement was not “based on” a Guidelines sentencing range. Under Justice Sotomayor's opinion, Epps's sentence was not based on a Guidelines sentencing range because Epps's plea agreement did not make “clear that the basis for the specified term is a Guidelines sentencing range.” 131 S.Ct. at 2697 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.). And of course, under the four-Justice opinion by Chief Justice Roberts, Epps's sentence was not based on a Guidelines sentencing range because Rule 11(c)(1)(C) sentences are, in those Justices' view, never based on a Guidelines sentencing range.

Epps never grapples with that critical point. Nor do Judge Rogers and Judge Williams address that reality in their opinions respecting the denial of en banc review.

In his opinion respecting denial of en banc, Judge Williams says that, under King, the dissent in a splintered decision does not play any role in the Marks analysis. But that is not what King said. To be sure, as Judge Williams notes, King said that we cannot “combine a dissent with a concurrence to form a Marks majority.” 950 F.2d at 783. In other words, looking to just the concurrence and dissent alone will never be enough to determine whether one of the opinions is the binding opinion under Marks. As I have explained, an opinion is the binding opinion only when it will lead to results with which a majority of the Court would agree in all future cases. And that analysis can be logically conducted only by looking at all of the opinions in the Supreme Court case at issue.
In the rare cases where the Marks analysis shows that there was no binding opinion, then the principle that I have described as the Marks corollary necessarily applies. For such cases, King did not say or purport to say that the views of the dissenters in the Supreme Court case are irrelevant. Put simply, I do not read King to direct that we decide a case contrary to how a majority of the Supreme Court in the governing precedent would decide the case.

* * *

In the event all of the above discussion is a bit difficult to follow, just focus on one key point: If the approaches of the nine Justices in Freeman were applied to Epps's case, Epps would lose. That's because Epps would lose under the approaches of Justice Sotomayor and the four dissenters. Yet under this Court's decision in Epps, Epps magically has won. In my view, that cannot be correct. How can it be consistent with vertical stare decisis to choose an approach that contradicts the will of a majority of the Supreme Court as expressed in the governing precedent?

I have great respect for my two distinguished colleagues in the Epps majority. And I recognize that Marks can sometimes seem like a Rubik's Cube. But in my view, the Epps decision jumped the rails. To be clear, I certainly do not believe that my colleagues are deliberately flouting Supreme Court precedent. Rather, I simply believe that they have adopted a mistaken approach to Marks that in turn will lead to our deciding certain cases in a manner inconsistent with Supreme Court precedent.

In his en banc petition, Duvall naturally seeks the benefit of the Epps holding. After all, the relevant facts of his case are indistinguishable from Epps. But in light of my views about Epps, I am obviously not inclined to ditch Duvall—a case that I believe was decided correctly—in favor of Epps. So I have voted to deny Duvall's en banc petition. For its part, the Government has let our decisions in Epps and Duvall co-exist for now, but the Government presumably will seek en banc in an appropriate future case. If the proper case arises, I will vote to reconsider Epps en banc, to overrule it, and to make clear that, as every other court of appeals has held, we must follow Justice Sotomayor's binding opinion in Freeman.

WILLIAMS, Senior Circuit Judge, concurring in the denial of en banc.

I have not asked for a vote on whether the panel opinion should be reviewed en banc, and write here only to discuss Judge Kavanaugh's suggestion that the related decision in United States v. Epps, 707 F.3d 337 (D.C.Cir.2013), be so reviewed on the first possible occasion.

Judge Kavanaugh argues that Justice Sotomayor's opinion in Freeman v. United States, ––– U.S. ––––, 131 S.Ct. 2685, 180 L.Ed.2d 519 (2011), states the “narrowest” grounds for allowing relief under 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2), as applied to plea agreements under Rule 11(c)(1)(C) of the Federal Rules of Criminal Procedure, and is therefore controlling Supreme Court precedent. Judge Kavanaugh argues that Epps 's analysis of when a splintered decision of the Supreme Court produces a binding precedent is inconsistent not only with the Supreme Court's decision in Marks v. United States, 430 U.S. 188, 193, 97 S.Ct. 990, 51 L.Ed.2d 260 (1977), but with our interpretation of Marks in King v. Palmer, 950 F.2d 771, 781 (D.C.Cir.1991). I shall address first, my understanding of Marks and King, and their application in Epps; and second, Judge Kavanaugh's critique of King.

It is perfectly true that Marks used the metaphor “narrow” to describe the circumstances where one opinion of a splintered set is binding, see, e.g., 430 U.S. at 193, 97 S.Ct. 990, but in King we gave that metaphor an analytical interpretation. Specifically, we held that one of several opinions in a decision is binding precedent only when the cases governed by its rule represent a subset of the cases governed by the other opinion(s) prevailing in the decision.

Without King 's requirement that one be a subset of the other, the idea of “narrowness” is inherently confusing and in fact indeterminate. That is because its application requires guesswork as to the distribution of situations governed by the rules. Let's assume Rules A and B, each setting out grounds for relief (or any specific outcome) and partially overlapping, as in the illustration below:


IMAGE

As I have drawn Rule B's sphere distinctly smaller than Rule A's, Rule B appears “narrower.” But the fact of a non-overlapping area for Rule B creates a measurement problem. How do we know that B's non-overlap area is smaller than A's? Moreover, why should Rule B's set of outcomes be viewed as the valid set where they fail to overlap with those produced under Rule A?

This of course describes the situation in Freeman. As the panel opinion in Epps recognized, there are cases where Justice Sotomayor's rule calls for relief and the plurality's does not. See Epps, 707 F.3d at 350–51 (citing United States v. Duvall, 705 F.3d 479, 487–89 (D.C.Cir.2013) (Williams, J., concurring in the judgment)). These are cases where the parties' agreement rests the sentence on a Guidelines provision that has been changed (calling for eligibility for relief under Justice Sotomayor's opinion), but the court, though imposing the agreed sentence, rests it upon another Guideline that the Sentencing Commission has left undisturbed.

Contrary to Judge Kavanaugh's suggestion, see Kavanaugh, J., ante at 614–16, Freeman does not satisfy what I earlier called the “weak” reading of King v. Palmer, see Duvall, 705 F.3d at 487 (Williams, J., concurring in the judgment). Cases producing an outcome in favor of the defendant under Justice Sotomayor's opinion would not invariably yield an outcome in his favor under the plurality. In my concurrence in Duvall, I used an example of the interplay between the defendant's alleged status as a career offender and the sentence associated with the relevant quantity of crack cocaine. In that hypo, the parties choose a Guidelines sentence via the crack cocaine quantity but ignore the career offender status (perhaps because there are procedural defects in previous convictions not worth the trouble of litigation), but the sentencing judge finds the career offender status applicable. They arrive at the same sentence, and the judge “accepts” the sentence agreed on by the parties by pronouncing the agreed-upon sentence. The Sentencing Commission subsequently lowers the penalty associated with the relevant quantity of crack distribution.

In such a case, the Freeman plurality would deny relief, as the sentencing court will have made clear that the sentence was not “based on a sentencing range that has been subsequently lowered by the Sentencing Commission.” 18 U.S.C. § 3582(c)(2). But Justice Sotomayor would grant relief—in her view, it is only the agreement that matters. As I said in my Duvall concurrence, “Cases such as this will occur any time the parties to a Rule 11(c)(1)(C) agreement agree to ignore some aspect of an alleged offense that would trigger a mandatory minimum or a mandatory enhancement that the sentencing judge deems inappropriate to ignore, but the agreement yields an ultimate sentence that the judge regards as otherwise ‘sufficient, but not greater than necessary,’ to achieve the goals of sentencing as required by 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a).” Duvall, 705 F.3d at 488 (Williams, J., concurring in the judgment). Thus the Freeman opinions on § 3582(c)(2) present the sort of case reflected in the diagram above. In such cases, the simple vision of relative “narrowness” becomes a matter of guesswork as to the distribution of cases among the various possible types.

Of course, even to suppose that such an estimated quantitative disparity would justify treating the “narrower” opinion as controlling rests on a dubious simplifying assumption: that a rule could be characterized as narrower merely because it called for relief in fewer situations. It is not obvious why such a purely quantitative approach would represent a sensible view of “narrow.”

The conditions that we laid out in King for the application of Marks leave no such ambiguity. Where (1) Rule B calls for relief in every case where Rule A does, and (2) Rule B calls for relief in no other cases, Rule B is clearly “narrower” than Rule A. The situation satisfying these criteria is illustrated below:


IMAGE

Here the proposition that Rule B is narrower than Rule A is completely independent of the distribution of factual patterns. It is, in fact, the relationship between the opinions at issue in Marks (to wit, the opinions in A Book Named “John Cleland's Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasure” v. Attorney General of Massachusetts, 383 U.S. 413, 86 S.Ct. 975, 16 L.Ed.2d 1 (1966)). By contrast, when the Supreme Court opinions yielding a result are on different wavelengths, as in Freeman and in the Supreme Court case at issue in King (namely Pennsylvania v. Delaware Valley Citizens' Council for Clean Air, 483 U.S. 711, 107 S.Ct. 3078, 97 L.Ed.2d 585 (1987)), characterizing one as narrower than the other is just a kind of judicial force majeure.

Judge Kavanaugh repeatedly asserts that the Freeman plurality “ always ” calls for eligibility under § 3582(c)(2) because the judge is necessarily applying a Guidelines range. Opinion of Kavanaugh, J., at 607–08, 612, 614 n. 5. But that assertion overlooks the requirement of § 3582 (c)(2) that the sentence in question have been based on “a sentencing range that has been subsequently lowered by the Sentencing Commission ....” In the class of cases discussed above, the parties' agreement has based the sentence on a range that has been lowered (controlling under Justice Sotomayor's opinion), but the court has based its sentence (controlling under the plurality) on one that has not. Accordingly, Justice Sotomayor's rule is not exclusively a subset of the plurality's.

To put it another way, while the plurality may always find that a sentence was based on a Guidelines range, it is not the case that in every situation where Justice Sotomayor finds a sentence to have been based on a Guideline that has been changed the plurality will do so. To find this fact immaterial to the application of King to Freeman, as Judge Kavanaugh appears to do, is to distort the nature of the dispute in Freeman. It would mean that a court purporting to apply Freeman could, after scrutinizing the plea agreement to determine whether a defendant's sentence was based on the Guidelines, then look either to the plea agreement or to the analysis of the sentencing judge in assessing whether the defendant was sentenced within a Guidelines range lowered by the Commission. That clearly was not what Justice Sotomayor had in mind; her assessment of defendant Freeman's eligibility for a sentence reduction under § 3582(c)(2) took no account of the reasoning of the sentencing judge. See Freeman, 131 S.Ct. at 2699–2700.

Judge Kavanaugh is also mistaken to suggest that Freeman can be shoehorned under King through use of the phrase “applicable guideline range” from the Application Note to § 1B1.10 of the Guidelines. See Opinion of Kavanaugh, J., at 614–15. How Justice Sotomayor might read “applicable guideline range,” which is made relevant through § 3582(c)(2)'s requirement that the requested sentence revision be “consistent with applicable policy statements issued by the Sentencing Commission” (plus the Application Note itself), is irrelevant to whether Freeman meets King 's requirements for establishing binding precedent: none of the opinions in Freeman purports to address the meaning of the Application Note to § 1B1.10 or its relationship to § 3582(c)(2). Rather, Freeman addressed only the requirement of § 3582(c)(2) that a sentence be “based on a sentencing range that has subsequently been lowered by the Sentencing Commission.”

Thus the proper application of King to Freeman need consider only whether the plurality would find that a defendant's sentence was based on a subsequently reduced Guidelines range in every instance where Justice Sotomayor would. King—and Marks, for that matter—are concerned only with the discrete questions actually addressed in the splintered opinions from which precedent is sought. Judge Kavanaugh's alternative would find a binding precedent (or deny one) with respect to one issue based on speculation as to how a justice might rule on an analytically distinct issue that the splintered opinions had no cause to examine.

The proper application of King undeniably means that some Supreme Court decisions yield no binding precedent, but that reality does not trigger vertical stare decisis concerns of the sort that trouble Judge Kavanaugh. Such instances are similar to a 4–4 split that affirms the lower court's opinion but does not supply a national rule governing future litigation. See, e.g., John Wiley & Sons, Inc. v. Kirtsaeng, 654 F.3d 210, 218 (2d Cir.2011) (citing the lack of binding authority produced by the 4–4 split in Costco Wholesale Corp. v. Omega, S.A., ––– U.S. ––––, 131 S.Ct. 565, 178 L.Ed.2d 470 (2010)). Of course, as actually occurred in Wiley, the Supreme Court may follow its splintered decision with a case that resolves the issue. See Kirtsaeng v. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., ––– U.S. ––––, 133 S.Ct. 1351, 185 L.Ed.2d 392 (2013) (resolving the issue 6–3).

Moreover, where the Court resolves a case with a splintered decision and a binding precedent cannot be found under Marks/King, the disarray among Supreme Court opinions is in important ways akin to the situation where one or more (indeed, perhaps all but one) courts of appeals have resolved an issue one way. In that case it is the duty of a court of appeals facing the issue de novo to resolve it de novo, with of course due recognition of the insights and arguments reflected in the opinions of other courts. That independent approach allows the issue to “percolate” and facilitates ultimate Supreme Court resolution on the basis of a broad pallet of lower court reasoning. Cf. United States v. Mendoza, 464 U.S. 154, 160, 104 S.Ct. 568, 78 L.Ed.2d 379 (1984) (“Allowing only one final adjudication [on a specified legal issue] would deprive this Court of the benefit it receives from permitting several courts of appeals to explore a difficult question before this Court grants certiorari.”). Similarly, where the justices produce splintered opinions that fail to satisfy King 's “subset” principle, the process of continued percolation through independent lower court reasoning yields important value.

Judge Kavanaugh's quest for binding Supreme Court precedent leads him to propose that when lower courts are confronted with such complete disarray that no single view meets even his standards (see Opinion of Kavanaugh, J., at 611–12 (alluding to “no-narrowest-opinion cases”)), they should “strive to decide the case before them in a way consistent with how the Supreme Court's opinions in the relevant precedent would resolve the current case.” Well, of course, that is what we always try to do. But the question is whether, looking at a set of opinions that reveal no common core, we should pretend that they have offered a unified body of coherent reasoning and treat that synthetic body of reasoning as binding precedent. Pursuing that approach, lower courts would look more like lower officials seeking to discern the intent of their superiors than like judges engaged in discerning and applying rules of law. Courts are still, or should be, institutions of reason, not will.

Judge Kavanaugh's proposed rule for resolving a case where there is no “narrowest” opinion, which entails “run[ning] the facts and circumstances of the current case” through the tests proposed by the various factions of the splintered decision on a case-by-case basis to produce “the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached,” Opinion of Kavanaugh, J., at 611, explicitly contemplates including the opinions of dissenting justices in the construction of such a “majority.” See id. at 611–12 (citing Rapanos v. United States, 547 U.S. 715, 810, 126 S.Ct. 2208, 165 L.Ed.2d 159 (2006) (Stevens, J., concurring)), 10 (“When [Justice Sotomayor] concludes that a plea agreement was not based on the Guidelines, she would agree with the result reached under Chief Justice Roberts's opinion for four Justices.”), 16–17 (“[C]ontrary to Epps 's assertion, Justice Sotomayor's opinion would not reach a different result than Justice Kennedy's opinion or Chief Justice Roberts's opinion in those career offender or mandatory minimum circumstances.”) (emphasis added).

“Foolproof” and “common sense” as Judge Kavanaugh believes this case-by-case majority-seeking approach to be, Opinion of Kavanaugh, J., at 611, it is in fact prohibited by King, which stated plainly that “we do not think we are free to combine a dissent with a concurrence to form a Marks majority,” 950 F.2d at 783. It is telling that one of the two circuits that have embraced the idea of reliance on dissenting opinions expressly acknowledged that King precludes such an approach. See United States v. Johnson, 467 F.3d 56, 65 (1st Cir.2006). Although some individual justices of the Supreme Court appear to have endorsed the idea of relying on dissents, see, e.g., Rapanos, 547 U.S. at 810, 126 S.Ct. 2208 (Stevens, J., concurring); Waters v. Churchill, 511 U.S. 661, 685, 114 S.Ct. 1878, 128 L.Ed.2d 686 (1994) (Souter, J., concurring), the Court as a whole has never contradicted King 's prohibition on counting dissenters. For that reason, Judge Kavanaugh's approach is unavailable to this court (unless we re- en banc King, which Judge Kavanaugh does not propose). That there is no Supreme Court decision embracing such a viewpoint is not surprising. Dissenting judges enjoy something of the liberty of a gadfly, as the outcome does not in fact depend on what they say. Dissents of course often prove bellwethers, but until they do so, they may inspire but not guide.

In short, the relationship between the opinions in Freeman precludes a finding that the Supreme Court has provided binding authority on this aspect of § 3582. Judge Kavanaugh frames his argument as advocating an en banc to overrule Epps, but in fact his objection is to the principle of King v. Palmer. In its place, he proposes a variation of Marks that requires a kind of lower-court clairvoyance into the minds of justices in future Supreme Court majorities. Yet he offers neither a compelling reason to adopt this new rule, nor evidence that King has caused the slightest difficulty in the twenty-two years since its adoption. King in fact supplied needed clarification for the challenge presented by splintered Supreme Court decisions; I see no reason to drop it now.


Summaries of

United States v. Duvall

United States Court of Appeals FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT
Aug 13, 2013
740 F.3d 604 (D.C. Cir. 2013)

recognizing " Marks applies when the concurrence posits a narrow test to which the plurality must necessarily agree as a logical consequence of its own, broader position"

Summary of this case from In re Avery

In United States v. Duvall, 740 F.3d 604 (D.C. Cir. 2013), then-Judge Kavanaugh discussed the rare circumstance where there is "no 'narrowest' opinion that would identify how a majority of the Supreme Court would resolve all future cases" because no opinion has "adopted a legal standard that would produce results with which a majority of the Court in that case necessarily would agree."

Summary of this case from Schaszberger v. Am. Fed'n of State Cnty.

debating which opinion controls in the Court's 4-1-4 decision in Freeman v. United States , 564 U.S. 522, 131 S.Ct. 2685, 180 L.Ed.2d 519

Summary of this case from Preterm-Cleveland v. McCloud

arguing "lower court ... must strive to reach the result that a majority of the Supreme Court would have reached in the current case" by "run[ning] the facts and circumstances of the current case through the various tests articulated by the Supreme Court in the binding case"

Summary of this case from Manning v. Caldwell

using a Venn diagram to explain why "[w]ithout King's requirement that one [opinion] be a subset of the other [opinion], the idea of 'narrowness' is inherently confusing and in fact indeterminate"

Summary of this case from Montgomery v. Rosen

arguing that Marks holdings must be “middle-ground opinion”

Summary of this case from In re Jones
Case details for

United States v. Duvall

Case Details

Full title:UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, APPELLEE v. DAVID A. DUVALL, ALSO KNOWN AS TONE…

Court:United States Court of Appeals FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT

Date published: Aug 13, 2013

Citations

740 F.3d 604 (D.C. Cir. 2013)

Citing Cases

United States v. Guillen

And its precedential force is absolute: "The binding opinion from a splintered decision is as authoritative…

United States v. Lamont

" (footnote omitted)). Although Epps places the Circuit "out of step with every other court of appeals that…